Download PDF
ads:
A History of Political Economy
John Kells Ingram
1888
Chapter One: Introductory
Chapter Two: Ancient Times
Chapter Three: The Middle Ages
Chapter Four: Modern Times: First and Second Phases
Chapter Five: Third Modern Phase: System of Natural Liberty
Chapter Six: The Historical School
Chapter Seven: Conclusion
Chapter I
Introductory
In the present condition of Political Economy, the production of new dogmatic treatises on the
subject does not appear to be opportune. There are many works, accessible to every one, in which,
with more or less of variation in details, what is known as the "orthodox" or "classical" system is
expounded. But there exists in England and other countries widespread dissatisfaction with that
system, and much difference of opinion with respect both to the method and the doctrines of
Economic Science. There is, in fact, good reason to believe that this department of social theory has
entered on a transition stage, and is destined ere long to undergo a considerable transformation.
But the new body of thought which will replace, or at least profoundly modify, the old, has not yet
been fully elaborated. The attitude of mind which these circumstances seem to prescribe is that of
pause and retrospection. It is thought that our position will be rendered clearer and our further
progress facilitated by tracing historically, and from a general point of view, the course of
speculation regarding economic phenomena, and contemplating the successive forms of opinion
conceding them in relation to the periods at which they were respectively evolved. And this is the
task undertaken in the following pages.
Such a study is in harmony with the best intellectual tendencies of our age, which is, more than
anything else, characterised by the universal supremacy of the historical spirit. To such a degree
has this spirit permeated all our modes of thinking, that with respect to every branch of knowledge,
no less than with respect to every institution and every form of human activity, we almost
instinctively ask, not merely what is its existing condition, but what were its earliest discoverable
germs, and what has been the course of its development? The assertion of J. B. Say(1) that the
history of Political Economy is of little value, being for the most part a record of absurd and justly
exploded opinions, belongs to a system of ideas already obsolete, and requires at the present time
no formal refutation.(2) It deserves notice only as reminding us that we must discriminate between
history and antiquarianism: what from the first had no significance it is mere pedantry to study now.
We need concern ourselves only with those modes of thinking which have prevailed largely and
seriously influenced practice in the past, or in which we can discover the roots of the present and
the future.
When we thus place ourselves at the point of view of history, it becomes unnecessary to discuss the
definition of Political Economy, or to enlarge on its method, at the outset. It will suffice to conceive it
as the theory of social wealth, or to accept provisionally Say's definition, which makes it the science
of the production, distribution, and consumption of wealth. Any supplementary ideas which require
to be taken into account will be suggested in the progress of our survey, and the determination of
the proper method of economic research will be treated as one of the principal results of the
historical evolution of the science.
The history of Political Economy must of course be distinguished from the economic history of
mankind, or of any separate portion of our race. The study of the succession of economic facts
themselves is one thing; the study of the succession of theoretic ideas concerning the facts is
another. And it is with the latter alone that we are here directly concerned. But these two branches
ads:
Livros Grátis
http://www.livrosgratis.com.br
Milhares de livros grátis para download.
of research, though distinct, yet stand in the closest relation to each other. The rise and the form of
economic doctrines have been largely conditioned by the practical situation, needs, and tendencies
of the corresponding epochs. With each important social change new economic questions have
presented themselves; and the theories prevailing in each period have owed much of their influence
to the fact that they seemed to offer solutions of the urgent problems of the age. Again, every
thinker, however in some respects he may stand above or before his contemporaries, is yet a child
of his time, and cannot be isolated from the social medium in which he lives and moves. He will
necessarily be affected by the circumstances which surround him, and in particular by the practical
exigencies of which his fellows feel the strain. This connection of theory with practice haS its
advantages and its dangers. It tends to give a real and positive character to theoretic inquiry; but it
may also be expected to produce exaggerations in 'doctrine, to lend undue prominence to particular
sides of the truth, and to cause transitory situations or temporary expedients to be regarded as
universally normal conditions.
There are other relations which we must not overlook in tracing the progress of economic opinion.
The several branches of the science of society are so closely connected that the history of no one of
them can with perfect rationality be treated apart, though such a treatment is recommended --
indeed necessitated -- by practical utility. The movement of economic thought is constantly and
powerfully affected by the prevalent mode of thinking, and even the habitual tone of sentiment, on
social subjects generally. All the intellectual manifestations of a period in relation to human
questions have a kindred character, and bear a certain stamp of homogeneity, which is vaguely
present to our minds when we speak of the spirit of the age, Social speculation again, and economic
research as one branch of it, is both through its philosophic method and through its doctrine under
the influence of the sciences which in the order of development precede the social, especially of the
science of organic nature.
It is of the highest importance to bear in mind these several relations of economic research both to
external circumstance and to other spheres of contemporary thought, because by keeping them in
view we shall be led to form less absolute and therefore juster estimates of the successive phases
of opinion. Instead of merely praising or blaming these according to the degrees of their accordance
with a predetermined standard of doctrine, we shall view them as elements in an ordered series, to
be studied mainly with respect to their filiation, their opportuneness, and their influences. We shall
not regard each new step in this theoretic development as implying an unconditional negation of
earlier views, which often had a relative justification, resting, as they did, on a real, though narrower,
basis of experience, or assuming the existence of a different social order. Nor shall we consider all
the theoretic positions now occupied as definitive; for the practical system of life which they tacitly
assume is itself susceptible of change, and destined, without doubt, more or less to undergo it.
Within the limits of a sketch like the present these considerations cannot be fully worked out; but an
effort will be made to keep them in view, and to mark the relations here indicated wherever their
influence is specially important or interesting.
The particular situation and tendencies of the several thinkers whose names are associated with
economic doctrines have, of course, modified in a greater or less degree the spirit or form of those
doctrines. Their relation to special predecessors, their native temperament, their early training, their
religious prepossessions and political partialities, have all had their effects. To these we shall in
some remarkable instances direct attention; but, in the main, they are, for our present purpose,
secondary and subordinate. The ensemble must preponderate over the individual; and the
constructors of theories must be regarded as organs of a common intellectual and social movement.
The history of economic inquiry is most naturally divided into the three great periods of (1) the
ancient, (2) the mediaeval, and (3) the modern worlds. In the two former, this branch of study could
exist only in a rudimentary state. It is evident that for any considerable development of social theory
two conditions must be fulfilled. First, the phenomena must have exhibited themselves on a
sufficiently extended scale to supply adequate matter for observation, and afford a satisfactory basis
for scientific generalisations; and secondly, whilst the spectacle is thus provided, the spectator must
have been trained for his task, and armed with the appropriate aids and instruments of research,
that is to say, there must have been such a previous cultivation of the simpler sciences as will have
both furnished the necessary data of doctrine and prepared the proper methods of investigation.
Sociology requires to use for its purposes theorems which belong to the domains of physics and
biology, and which it must borrow from their professors; and, on the logical side, the methods which
it has to employ -- deductive, observational, comparative -- must have been previously shaped in the
ads:
cultivation of mathematics and the study of the inorganic world or of organisms less complex than
the social. Hence it is plain that, though some laws or tendencies of society must have been forced
on men's attention in every age by practical exigencies which could not be postponed, and though
the questions thus raised must have received some empirical solution, a really scientific sociology
must be the product of a very advanced stage of intellectual development. And this is true of the
economic, as of other branches of social theory. We shall therefore content ourselves with a general
outline of the character of economic thought in antiquity and the Middle Ages, and of the conditions
which determined that character.
Notes:
1. "Que pourrions-nous gagner à recueillir des opinions absurdes, des doctrines décriées et qui
meritent de l'être? Il serait à la fois inutile et fastidieux." Écon. Pol. Pratique, IXme Partie. The
"cependant" which follows does not really modify this judgment.
2. See Roscher's Geschichte der National-oekoomik in Deutschland, Vorrede.
Chapter 2
Ancient Times
The earliest surviving expressions of thought on economic subjects have come down to us from the
Oriental theocracies. The general spirit of the corresponding type of social life consisted in taking
imitation for the fundamental principle of education, and consolidating nascent civilisation by
heredity of the different functions and professions, or even by a system of castes, hierarchically
subordinated to each other according to the nature of their respective offices, under the common
supreme direction of the sacerdotal caste. This last was charged with the traditional stock of
conceptions, and their application for purposes of discipline. It sought to realise a complete
regulation of human life in all its departments on the basis of this transmitted body of practical ideas.
Conservation is the principal task of this social order, and its most remarkable quality is stability,
which tends to degenerate into stagnation. But there can be no doubt that the useful arts were long,
though slowly, progressive under this regime, from which they were inherited by the later
civilisations -- the system of classes or castes maintaining the degree of division of labour which had
been reached in those early periods. The leading members of the corporations which presided over
the theocracies without doubt gave much earnest thought to the conduct of industry, which, unlike
war, did not imperil their political pre-eminence by developing a rival class. But, conceiving life as a
whole, and making its regulation their primary aim, they naturally considered most the social
reactions which industry is fitted to exercise. The moral side of economics is the one they habitually
contemplate, or (what is not the same) the economic side of morals. They abound in those warnings
against greed and the haste to be rich which religion and philosophy have in all ages seen to be
necessary. They insist on honesty in mutual dealings, on just weights and measures, on the faithful
observance of contracts. They admonish against the pride and arrogance apt to be generated by
riches, against undue prodigality and self-indulgence, and enforce the duties of justice and
beneficence towards servants and inferiors. Whilst, in accordance with the theological spirit, the
personal acquisition of wealth is in general thesis represented as determined by divine wills, its
dependence on individual diligence and thrift is emphatically taught. There is indeed in the fully
developed theocratic systems a tendency to carry precept, which there differs little from command,
to an excessive degree of minuteness -- to prescribe in detail the time, the mode, and the
accompaniments of almost every act of every member of the community. This system of
exaggerated surveillance is connected with the union, or rather confusion, of the spiritual and
temporal powers, whence it results that many parts of the government of society are conducted by
direct injunction or restraint, which at a later stage are intrusted to general intellectual and moral
influences.
The practical economic enterprises of Greek and Roman antiquity could not, even independently of
any special adverse influences, have competed in magnitude of scale or variety of resource with
those of modern times. The unadvanced condition of physical science prevented a large application
of the less obvious natural powers to production, or the extensive use of machinery, which has
acquired such an immense development as a factor in modern industry. The imperfection of
geographical knowledge and of the means of communication and transport were impediments to the
growth of foreign commerce. These obstacles arose necessarily out of the mere immaturity of the
industrial life of the periods in question. But more deeply rooted impediments to a vigorous and
expansive economic practical system existed in the characteristic principles of the civilisation of
antiquity. Some writers have attempted to set aside the distinction between the ancient and modern
worlds as imaginary or unimportant, and, whilst admitting the broad separation between ourselves
and the theocratic peoples of the East, to represent the Greeks and Romans as standing on a
substantially similar ground of thought, feeling, and action with the Western populations of our own
time. But this is a serious error, arising from the same too exclusive pre-occupation with the
cultivated classes and with the mere speculative intellect which has often led to an undue
disparagement of the Middle Ages. There is this essential difference between the spirit and life of
ancient and of modern communities, that the former were organised for war, the latter during their
whole history have increasingly tended to be organised for industry, as their practical end and aim.
The profound influence of these differing conditions on every form of human activity must never be
overlooked or forgotten. With the military constitution of ancient societies the institution of slavery
was essentially connected. Far from being an excrescence on the contemporary system of life, as it
was in the modern West Indies or the United States of America, it was so entirely in harmony with
that life that the most eminent thinkers regarded it as no less indispensable than inevitable. It does,
indeed, seem to have been a temporary necessity, and on the whole, regard being had to what
might have taken its place, a relative good. But it was attended with manifold evils. It led to the
prevalence amongst the citizen class of a contempt for industrial occupations; every form of
production, with a partial exception in favour of agriculture, was branded as unworthy of a free man
-- the only noble forms of activity being those directly connected with public life, whether military or
administrative. Labour was degraded by the relegation of most departments of it to the servile class,
above whom the free artisans were but little elevated in general esteem. The producers being thus
for the most part destitute of intellectual cultivation and excluded from any share in civic ideas,
interests, or efforts, were unfitted in character as well as by position for the habits of skilful
combination and vigorous initiation which the progress of industry demands. To this must be added
that the comparative insecurity of life and property arising out of military habits, and the consequent
risks which attended accumulation, were grave obstructions to the formation of large capitals, and to
the establishment of an effective system of credit. These causes conspired with the undeveloped
state of knowledge and of social relations in giving to the economic life of the ancients the limitation
and monotony which contrast so strongly with the inexhaustible resource, the ceaseless expansion,
and the thousandfold variety of the same activities in the modern world. It is, of course, absurd to
expect incompatible qualities in any social system; each system must be estimated according to the
work it has to do. Now the historical vocation of the ancient civilisation was to be accomplished, not
through industry, but through war, which was in the end to create a condition of things admitting of
its own elimination and of the foundation of a regime based on pacific activity.
THE GREEKS
This office was, however, reserved for Rome, as the final result of her system of conquest; the
military activity of Greece, though continuous, was incoherent and sterile, except in the defence
against Persia, and did not issue in the accomplishment of any such social mission. It was,
doubtless, the inadequacy of the warrior life, under these conditions, to absorb the faculties of the
race, that threw the energies of its most eminent members into the channel of intellectual activity,
and produced a singularly rapid evolution of the aesthetic, philosophic, and scientific germs
transmitted by the theocratic societies.
In the Works and Days of Hesiod, we find an order of thinking in the economic sphere very similar to
that of the theocracies. With a recognition of the divine disposing power, and traditional rules of
sacerdotal origin, is combined practical sagacity embodied in precept or proverbial saying. But the
development of abstract thought, beginning from the time of Thales, soon gives to Greek culture its
characteristic form, and marks a new epoch in the intellectual history of mankind.
The movement was now begun, destined to mould the whole future of humanity, which, gradually
sapping the old hereditary structure of theological convictions, tended to the substitution of rational
theories in every department of speculation. The eminent Greek thinkers, while taking a deep
interest in the rise of positive science, and most of them studying the only science -- that of
geometry -- then assuming its definitive character, were led by the social exigencies which always
powerfully affect great minds to study with special care the nature of man and the conditions of his
existence in society. These studies were indeed essentially premature; a long development of the
inorganic and vital sciences was necessary before sociology or morals could attain their normal
constitution. But by their prosecution amongst the Greeks a noble intellectual activity was kept alive,
and many of those partial lights obtained for which mankind cannot afford to wait. Economic
inquiries, along with others, tended towards rationality; Plutus was dethroned, and terrestrial
substituted for supernatural agencies. But such inquiries, resting on no sufficiently large basis of
practical life, could not attain any considerable results. The military constitution of society, and the
existence of slavery, which was related to it, leading, as we have seen, to a low estimate of
productive industry, turned away the habitual attention of thinkers from that domain. On the other
hand, the absorption of citizens in the life of the state, and their pre-occupation with party struggles,
brought questions relating to politics, properly so called, into special prominence. The principal
writers on social subjects are therefore almost exclusively occupied with the examination and
comparison of political constitutions, and with the search after the education best adapted to train
the citizen for public functions. And we find, accordingly, in them no systematic or adequate
handling of economic questions only some happy ideas and striking partial anticipations of later
research.
In their thinking on such questions, as on all sociological subjects, the following general features are
observable.
1. The individual is conceived as subordinated to the state, through which alone his nature can be
developed and completed, and to the maintenance and service of which all his efforts must be
directed. The great aim of all political thought is the formation of good citizens; every social question
is studied primarily from the ethical and educational point of view. The citizen is not regarded as a
producer, but only as a possessor, of material wealth; and this wealth is not esteemed for its own
sake or for the enjoyments it procures, but for the higher moral and public aims to which it may be
made subservient.
2. The state, therefore, claims and exercises a controlling and regulating authority over every sphere
of social life, including the economic, in order to bring individual action into harmony with the good of
the whole.
3. With these fundamental notions is combined a tendency to attribute to institutions and to
legislation an unlimited efficacy, as if society had no spontaneous tendencies, but would obey any
external impulse, if impressed upon it with sufficient force and continuity.
Every eminent social speculator had his ideal state, which approximated to or diverged from the
actual or possible, according to the degree in which a sense of reality and a positive habit of thinking
characterised the author.
The most celebrated of these ideal systems is that of Plato. In it the idea of the subordination of the
individual to the state appears in its most extreme form. Within that class of the citizens of his
republic who represent the highest type of life, community of property and of wives is established, as
the most effective means of suppressing the sense of private interest, and consecrating the
individual entirely to the public service. It cannot perhaps be truly said that his scheme was
incapable of realisation in an ancient community favourably situated for the purpose. But it would
soon be broken to pieces by the forces which would be developed in an industrial society. It has,
however, been the fruitful parent of modern Utopias, specially attractive as it is to minds in which the
literary instinct is stronger than the scientific judgment, in consequence of the freshness and
brilliancy of Plato's exposition and the unrivalled charm of his style. Mixed with what we should call
the chimerical ideas of his work, there are many striking and elevated moral conceptions, and, what
is more to our present purpose, some just economic analyses. In particular, he gives a correct
account of the division and combination of employments, as they naturally arise in society. The
foundation of the social organization he traces, perhaps, too exclusively to economic grounds, not
giving sufficient weight to the disinterested social impulses in men which tend to draw and bind them
together. But he explains clearly how the different wants and capacities of individuals demand and
give rise to mutual services, and how, by the restriction of each to the sort of occupation to which, by
his position, abilities, and training, he is best adapted, everything needful for the whole is more
easily and better produced or effected. In the spirit of all the ancient legislators he desires a self-
sufficing state, protected from unnecessary contacts with foreign populations, which might tend to
break down its internal organisation or to deteriorate the national character. Hence he
discountenances foreign trade, and with this view removes his ideal city to some distance from the
sea. The limits of its territory are rigidly fixed, and the population is restricted by the prohibition of
early marriages, by the exposure of infants, and by the maintenance of a determinate number of
individual lots of land in the hands of the citizens who cultivate the soil. These precautions are
inspired more by political and moral motives than by the %Malthusian fear of failure of subsistence.
Plato aims, as far as possible, at equality of property amongst the families of the community which
are engaged in the immediate prosecution of industry. This last class, as distinguished from the
governing and military classes, he holds, according to the spirit of his age, in but little esteem; he
regards their habitual occupations as tending to the degradation of the mind and the enfeeblement
of the body, and rendering those who follow them unfit for the higher duties of men and citizens. The
lowest forms of labour he would commit to foreigners and slaves. Again, in the spirit of ancient
theory, he wishes (Legg., v. 12) to banish the precious metals, as far as practicable, from use in
internal commerce, and forbids the lending of money on interest, leaving indeed to the free will of
the debtor even the repayment of the capital of the loan. All economic dealings he subjects to active
control on the part of the Government, not merely to prevent violence and fraud, but to check the
growth of luxurious habits, and secure to the population of the state a due supply of the necessaries
and comforts of life.
Contrasted with the exaggerated idealism of Plato is the somewhat limited but eminently practical
genius of Xenophon. In him the man of action predominates, but he has also a large element of the
speculative tendency and talent of the Greek. His treatise entitled Oeconomicus is well worth
reading for the interesting and animated picture it presents of some aspects of contemporary life,
and is justly praised by Sismondi for the spirit of mild philanthropy and tender piety which breathes
through it. But it scarcely passes beyond the bounds of domestic economy, though within that limit
its author exhibits much sound sense and sagacity. His precepts for the judicious conduct of private
property do not concern us here, nor his wise suggestions for the government of the family and its
dependents. Yet it is in this narrower sphere and in general in the concrete domain that his chief
excellence lies; to economics in their wider aspects he does not contribute much. He shares the
ordinary preference of his fellow-countrymen for agriculture over other employments, and is, indeed,
enthusiastic in his praises of it as promoting patriotic and religious feeling and a respect for property,
as furnishing the best preparation for military life, and as leaving sufficient time and thought
disposable to admit of considerable intellectual and political activity. Yet his practical sense leads
him to attribute greater importance than most other Greek writers to manufactures, and still more to
trade, to enter more largely on questions relating to their conditions and development, and to
bespeak for them the countenance and protection of the state. Though his views on the nature of
money are vague, and in some respects erroneous, he sees that its export in exchange for
commodities will not impoverish the community. He also insists on the necessity, with a view to a
flourishing commerce with other countries, of peace, of a courteous and respectful treatment of
foreign traders, and of a prompt and equitable decision of their legal suits. The institution of slavery
he of course recognises and does not disapprove; he even recommends, for the increase of the
Attic revenues, the hiring out of slaves by the state for labour in the mines, after branding them to
prevent their escape, the number of slaves being constantly increased by fresh purchases out of the
gains of the enterprise. (De Vect., 3, 4.)
Almost the whole system of Greek ideas up to the time of Aristotle is represented in his
encyclopaedic construction. Mathematical and astronomical science was largely developed at a
later stage, but in the field of social studies no higher point was ever attained by the Greeks than is
reached in the writings of this great thinker Both his gifts and his situation eminently favoured him in
the treatment of these subjects. He combined in rare measure a capacity for keen observation with
generalising power, and sobriety of judgment with ardour for the public good. All that was original or
significant in the political life of Hellas had run its course before his time or under his own eyes, and
he had thus a large basis of varied experience on which to ground his conclusions. Standing outside
the actual movement of contemporary public life, he occupied the position of thoughtful spectator
and impartial judge. He could not, indeed, for reasons already stated, any more than other Greek
speculators, attain a fully normal attitude in these researches. Nor could he pass beyond the sphere
of what is now called statical sociology; the idea of laws of the historical development of social
phenomena he scarcely apprehended, except in some small degree in relation to the succession of
political forms. But there is to be found in his writings a remarkable body of sound and valuable
thoughts on the constitution and working of the social organism The special notices of economic
subjects are neither so numerous nor so detailed as we should desire. Like all the Greek thinkers,
he recognises but one doctrine of the state, under which ethics, politics proper, and economics take
their place as departments, bearing to each other a very close relation, and having indeed their lines
of demarcation from each other not very distinctly marked. When wealth comes under
consideration, it is studied not as an end in itself, but with a view to the higher elements and ultimate
aims of the collective life.
The origin of society he traces, not to economic necessities, but to natural social impulses in the
human constitution. The nature of the social union, when thus established, being determined by the
partly spontaneous partly systematic combination of diverse activities, he respects the
independence of the latter whilst seeking to effect their convergence. He therefore opposes himself
to the suppression of personal freedom and initiative, and the excessive subordination of the
individual to the state, and rejects the community of property and wives proposed by Plato for his
governing class. The principle of private property he regards as deeply rooted in man, and the evils
which are alleged to result from the corresponding social ordinance he thinks ought really to be
attributed either to the imperfections of our nature or to the vices of other public institutions.
Community of goods must, in his view, tend to neglect of the common interest and to the
disturbance of social harmony.
Of the several classes which provide for the different wants of the society, those who are occupied
directly with its material needs -- the immediate cultivators of the soil, the mechanics and artificers --
are excluded from any share in the government of the state, as being without the necessary leisure
and cultivation, and apt to be debased by the nature of their occupations. In a celebrated passage
he propounds a theory of slavery, in which it is based on the universality of the relation between
command and obedience, and on the natural division by which the ruling is marked off from the
subject race. He regards the slave as having no independent will, but as an "animated tool" in the
hands of his master; and in his subjection to such control, if only it be intelligent, Aristotle holds that
the true well-being of the inferior as well as of the superior is to be found. This view, so shocking to
our modern sentiment, is of course not personal to Aristotle; it is simply the theoretic presentation of
the facts of Greek life, in which the existence of a body of citizens pursuing the higher culture and
devoted to the tasks of war and government was founded on the systematic degradation of a
wronged and despised class, excluded from all the higher offices of human beings and sacrificed to
the maintenance of a special type of society.
The methods of economic acquisition are divided by Aristotle into two, one of which has for its aim
the appropriation of natural products and their application to the material uses of the household;
under this head come hunting, fishing, cattle-rearing, and agriculture. With this primary and "natural"
method is, in some sense, contrasted the other to which Aristotle gives the name of "chrematistic,"
in which an active exchange of products goes on, and money comes into operation as its medium
and regulator. A certain measure of this "non-natural " method, as it may be termed in opposition to
the preceding and simpler form of industrial life, is accepted by Aristotle as a necessary extension of
the latter, arising out of increased activity of intercourse, and satisfying real wants. But its
development on the great scale, founded on the thirst for enjoyment and the unlimited desire of
gain, he condemns as unworthy and corrupting. Though his views on this subject appear to be
principally based on moral grounds, there are some indications of his having entertained the
erroneous opinion held by the physiocrats of the eighteenth century, that agriculture alone (with the
kindred arts above joined with it) is truly productive, whilst the other kinds of industry, which either
modify the products of nature or distribute them by way of exchange, however convenient and
useful they may be, make no addition to the wealth of the community.
He rightly regards money as altogether different from wealth, illustrating the difference by the story
of Midas. And he seems to have seen that money, though its use rests on a social convention, must
be composed of a material possessing an independent value of its own. That his views on capital
were indistinct appears from his famous argument against interest on loans, which is based on the
idea that money is barren and cannot produce money.
Like the other Greek social philosophers, Aristotle recommends to the care of Governments the
preservation of a due proportion between the extent of the civic territory and its population, and
relies on ante-nuptial continence, late marriages, and the prevention or destruction of births for the
due limitation of the number of citizens, the insufficiency of the latter being dangerous to the
independence and its superabundance to the tranquillity and good order of the state.
THE ROMANS
Notwithstanding the eminently practical, realistic, and utilitarian character of the Romans, there was
no energetic exercise of their powers in the economic field; they developed no large and many-
sided system of production and exchange. Their historic mission was military and political, and the
national energies were mainly devoted to the public service at home and in the field. To agriculture,
indeed, much attention was given from the earliest times, and on it was founded the existence of the
hardy population which won the first steps in the march to universal dominion. But in the course of
their history the cultivation of the soil by a native yeomanry gave place to the introduction, in great
numbers, of slave labourers acquired by their foreign conquests; and for the small properties of the
earlier period were substituted the vast estates -- the latifundia -- which, in the judgment of Pliny,
were the ruin of Italy.(1) The industrial arts and commerce (the latter, at least when not conducted
on a great scale) they regarded as ignoble pursuits, unworthy of free citizens; and this feeling of
contempt was not merely a prejudice of narrow or uninstructed minds, but was shared by Cicero and
others among the most liberal spirits of the nation.(2) As might be expected from the want of
speculative originality among the Romans, there is little evidence of serious theoretic inquiry on
economic subjects. Their ideas on these as on other social questions were for the most part
borrowed from the Greek thinkers. Such traces of economic thought as do occur are to be found in
(1) the philosophers, (2) the writers de re rustica, and (3) the jurists. It must, however, be admitted
that many of the passages in these authors referred to by those who assert the claim of the Romans
to a more prominent place in the history of the science often contain only obvious truths or vague
generalities.
In the philosophers, whom Cicero, Seneca, and the elder Pliny sufficiently represent (the last indeed
being rather a learned encyclopaedist or polyhistor than a philosopher), we find a general
consciousness of the decay of industry, the relaxation of morals, and the growing spirit of self-
indulgence amongst their contemporaries, who are represented as deeply tainted with the imported
vices of the conquered nations. This sentiment, both in these writers and in the poetry and
miscellaneous literature of their times, is accompanied by a half-factitious enthusiasm for agriculture
and an exaggerated estimate of country life and of early Roman habits, which are principally, no
doubt, to be regarded as a form of protest against existing abuses, and, from this point of view,
remind us of the declamations of Rousseau in a not dissimilar age. But there is little of larger or just
thinking on the prevalent economic evils and their proper remedies. Pliny, still further in the spirit of
Rousseau, is of opinion that the introduction of gold as a medium of exchange was a thing to be
deplored, and that the age of barter was preferable to that of money. He expresses views on the
necessity of preventing the efflux of money similar to those of the modern mercantile school -- views
which Cicero also, though not so clearly, appears to have entertained. Cato, Varro, and Columella
concern themselves more with the technical precepts of husbandry than with the general conditions
of industrial success and social well-being. But the two last named have the great merit of having
seen and proclaimed the superior value of free to slave labour, and Columella is convinced that to
the use of the latter the decline of the agricultural economy of the Romans was in a great measure
to be attributed. These three writers agree in the belief that it was chiefly by the revival and reform of
agriculture that the threatening inroads of moral corruption could be stayed, the old Roman virtues
fostered, and the foundations of the commonwealth strengthened. Their attitude is thus similar to
that of the French physiocrats invoking the improvement and zealous pursuit of agriculture alike
against the material evils and the social degeneracy of their time. The question of the comparative
merits of the large and small systems of cultivation appears to have been much discussed in the old
Roman, as in the modern European world; Columella is a decided advocate of the petite culture.
The jurists were led by the coincidence which sometimes takes place between their point of view
and that of economic science to make certain classifications and establish some more or less
refined distinctions which the modern economists have either adopted from them or used
independently. They appear also (though this has been disputed, Neri and Carli maintaining the
affirmative, Pagnini the negative) to have had correct notions of the nature of money as having a
value of its own, determined by economic conditions, and incapable of being impressed upon it by
convention or arbitrarily altered by public authority. But in general we find in these writers, as might
be expected, not so much the results of independent thought as documents illustrating the facts of
Roman economic life, and the historical policy of the nation with respect to economic subjects. From
the latter point of view they are of much interest; and by the information they supply as to the Course
of legislation relating to property generally, to sumptuary control, to the restrictions imposed on
spendthrifts, to slavery, to the encouragement of population, and the like, they give us much clearer
insight than we should otherwise possess into influences long potent in the history of Rome and of
the Western world at large. But, as it is with the more limited field of systematic thought on political
economy that we are here occupied, we cannot enter into these subjects. One matter, however,
ought to be adverted to, because it was not only repeatedly dealt with by legislation, but is treated
more or less fully by all Roman writers of note, namely, the interest on money loans. The rate was
fixed by the laws of the Twelve Tables; but lending on interest was afterwards (B.C. 341) entirely
prohibited by the Genucian Law, In the legislation of Justinian, rates were sanctioned varying from
four to eight per cent according to the nature of the case, the latter being fixed as the ordinary
mercantile rate, whilst compound interest was forbidden. The Roman theorists, almost without
exception, disapprove of lending on interest altogether. Cato, as Cicero tells us, thought it as bad as
murder ("Quid fenerari? Quid hominem occidere?" De Off, ii. 25); and Cicero, Seneca, Pliny,
Columella all join in condemning it. It is not difficult to see how in early states of society the trade of
money-lending becomes, and not unjustly, the object of popular odium; but that these writers, at a
period when commercial enterprise had made considerable progress, should continue to reprobate
it argues very imperfect or confused ideas on the nature and functions of capital. It is probable that
practice took little heed either of these speculative ideas or of legislation on the subject, which
experience shows can always be easily evaded. The traffic in money seems to have gone on all
through Roman history, and the rate to have fluctuated according to the condition of the market.
Looking back on the history of ancient economic speculation, we see that, as might be anticipated a
priori, the results attained in that field by the Greek and Roman writers were very scanty. As Dühring
has well remarked, the questions with which the science has to do were regarded by the ancient
thinkers rather from their political than their properly economic side. This we have already pointed
out with respect to their treatment of the subject of population, and the same may be seen in the
case of the doctrine of the division of labour, with which Plato and Aristotle are in some degree
occupied. They regard that principle as a basis of social classification, or use it in showing that
society is founded on a spontaneous co-operation of diverse activities. From the strictly economic
point of view, there are three important propositions which can be enunciated respecting that
division: -- (1) that its extension within any branch of production makes the products cheaper; (2)
that it is limited by the extent of the market; and (3) that it can be carried further in manufactures
than in agriculture. But we shall look in vain for these propositions in the ancient writers; the first
alone might be inferred from their discussions of the subject. It has been the tendency especially of
German scholars to magnify unduly the extent and value of the contributions of antiquity to
economic knowledge. The Greek and Roman authors ought certainly not to be omitted in any
account of the evolution of this branch of study. But it must be kept steadily in view that we find in
them only first hints or rudiments of general economic truths, and that the science is essentially a
modern one. We shall indeed see hereafter that it could not have attained its definitive constitution
before our own time.(3)
Notes:
1. "Locis, quae nunc, vix seminario exiguo militum relicto, servitia Romana ab solitudine vindicant."
-- Liv. vi. 12. "Villarum infinita spatia." Tac. Ann. iii. 53.
2. "Opifices omnes in sordida arte versantur; nec enim quidquam ingenuum habere potest officina."
Cic. de Off. i. 42. "Mercatura, si tenuis est, sordida putanda est: sin magna et copiosa, multa
undique apportans multisque sine vanitate impertiens, non est admodum vituperanda." -- Ibid.
"Quaestus omnis Patribus indecorus visus est." Liv. xxi. 63
3. On the Economic doctrines of the Ancients see Roscher's Essay Ueber das Verhältniss der
National÷konomie zum klassischen Alterthume in his Ansichten der Volkswirthschaft (1861).
Chapter 3
The Middle Ages
The Middle Ages (400-1300 A.D.) form a period of great significance in the economic, as in the
general, history of Europe, They represent a vast transition, in which the germs of a new world were
deposited, but in which little was fully elaborated. There is scarcely anything in the later movement
of European society which we do not find there, though as yet, for the most part, crude and
undeveloped. The medieval period was the object of contemptuous depreciation on the part of the
liberal schools of the last century, principally because it contributed so little to literature. But there
are things more important to mankind than literature. and the great men of the Middle Ages had
enough to do in other fields to occupy their utmost energies. The development of the Catholic
institutions and the gradual establishment and maintenance of a settled order after the dissolution of
the Western empire absorbed the powers of the thinkers and practical men of several centuries. The
first medieval phase, from the commencement of the fifth century to the end of the seventh, was
occupied with the painful and stormy struggle towards the foundation of the new ecclesiastical and
civil system; three more centuries were filled with the work of its consolidation and defence against
the assaults of nomad populations; only in the final phase, during the eleventh, twelfth, and
thirteenth centuries, when the unity of the West was founded by the collective action against
impending Moslem invasion, did it enjoy a sufficiently secure and stable existence to exhibit its
essential character and produce its noblest personal types. The elaboration of feudalism was,
indeed, in progress during the whole period, showing itself in the decomposition of power and the
hierarchical subordination of its several grades, the movement being only temporarily suspended in
the second phase by the salutary dictatorship of Charlemagne. But not before the first century of the
last phase was the feudal system fully constituted. In like manner, only in the final phase could the
effort of Catholicism after a universal discipline be carried out on the great scale -- an effort for ever
admirable though necessarily on the whole unsuccessful.
No large or varied economic activity was possible under the full ascendency of feudalism. That
organisation, as has been abundantly shown by philosophical historians, was indispensable for the
preservation of order and for public defence, and contributed important elements to general
civilization. But, whilst recognizing it as opportune and relatively beneficent, we must not expect
from it advantages inconsistent with its essential nature and historical office. The class which
predominated in it was not sympathetic with industry, and held the handicrafts in contempt, except
those subservient to war or rural sports. The whole practical life of the society was founded on
territorial property. the wealth of the lord consisted in the produce of his lands and the dues paid to
him in kind; this wealth was spent in supporting a body of retainers whose services were repaid by
their maintenance. There could be little room for manufactures, and less for commerce; and
agriculture was carried on with a view to the wants of the family, or at most of the immediate
neighbourhood, not to those of a wider market. The economy of the period was therefore simple,
and, in the absence of special motors from without, unprogressive.
In the latter portion of the Middle Ages several circumstances came into action which greatly
modified these conditions. The Crusades undoubtedly produced a powerful economic effect by
transferring in many cases the possessions of the feudal chiefs to the industrious classes, whilst by
bringing different nations and races into contact, by enlarging the horizon and widening the
conceptions of the populations, as well as by affording a special stimulus to navigation, they tended
to give a new activity to international trade. The independence of the towns and the rising
importance of the burgher class supplied a counterpoise to the power of the land aristocracy; and
the strength of these new social elements was increased by the corporate constitution given to the
urban industries, the police of the towns being also founded on the trade guilds, as that of the
country districts was on the feudal relations. The increasing demand of the towns for the products of
agriculture gave to the prosecution of that art a more extended and speculative character; and this
again led to improved methods of transport and communication. But the range of commercial
enterprise continued everywhere narrow, except in some favoured centres, such as the Italian
republics, in which, however, the growth of the normal habits of industrial life was impeded or
perverted by military ambition, which was not, in the case of those communities, checked as it was
elsewhere by the pressure of an aristocratic class.
Every great change of opinion on the destinies of man and the guiding principles of conduct must
react on the sphere of material interests; and the Catholic religion had a powerful influence on the
economic life of the Middle Ages. Christianity inculcates, perhaps, no more effectively than the
industry, thrift, older religions the special economic virtues of fidelity to engagements, obedience to
rightful authority; but it brought out more forcibly and presented more persistently the higher aims of
life, and so produced a more elevated way of viewing the different social relations. It purified
domestic life, a reform which has the most important economic results. It taught the doctrine of
fundamental human equality, heightened the dignity of labour, and preached with quite a new
emphasis the obligations of love, compassion, and forgiveness, and the claims of the poor. The
constant presentation to the general mind and conscience of these ideas, the dogmatic bases of
which were scarcely as yet assailed by scepticism, must have had a powerful effect in moralising
life. But to the influence of Christianity as a moral doctrine was added that of the Church as an
organization, charged with the application of the doctrine to men's daily transactions, Besides the
teachings of the sacred books, there was a mass of ecclesiastical legislation providing specific
prescriptions for the conduct of the faithful. And this legislation dealt with the economic as with other
provinces of social activity. In the Corpus Juris Canonici, which condenses the result of centuries of
study and effort, along with much else is set out what we may call the Catholic economic theory, if
we understand by theory, not a reasoned explanation of phenomena, but a body of ideas leading to
prescriptions for the guidance of conduct. Life is here looked at from the point of view of spiritual
well-being; the aim is to establish and maintain amongst men a true kingdom of God,
The canonists are friendly to the notion of a community of goods from the side of sentiment
("Dulcissima rerum possessio communis est"), though they regard the distinction of meum and tuum
as an institution necessitated by the fallen state of man. In cases of need the public authority is
justified in re-establishing pro hac vice the primitive community. The care of the poor is not a matter
of free choice; the relief of their necessities is debitum legale. Avaritia is, idolatry; cupiditas, even
when it does not grasp at what is another's, is the root of all evil, and ought to be not merely
regulated but eradicated. Agriculture and handiwork are viewed as legitimate modes of earning food
and clothing; but trade is regarded with disfavour, because it was held almost certainly to lead to
fraud: of agriculture it was said, "Deo non displicet"; but of the merchant, "Deo placere non potest."
The seller was bound to fix the price of his wares, not according to the market rate, as determined
by supply and demand, but according to their real value (justum pretium). He must not conceal the
faults of his merchandise, nor take advantage of the need or ignorance of the buyer to obtain from
him more than the fair price. Interest on money is forbidden; the prohibition of usury is, indeed, as
Roscher says, the centre of the whole canonistic system of economy, as well as the foundation of a
great part of the ecclesiastical jurisdiction. The question whether a transaction was or was not
usurious turning mainly on the intentions of the parties, the innocence or blameworthiness of
dealings in which money was lent became rightfully a subject of determination for the Church, either
by her casuists or in her courts.(1)
The foregoing principles point towards a noble ideal, but by their ascetic exaggeration they worked
in some directions as an impediment to industrial progress. Thus, whilst, with the increase of
production, a greater division of labour and a larger employment of borrowed capital naturally
followed, the laws on usury tended to hinder this expansion. Hence they were undermined by
various exceptions, or evaded by fictitious transactions. These laws were in fact dictated by, and
adapted to, early conditions-to a state of society in which money loans were commonly sought either
with a view to wasteful pleasures or for the relief of such urgent distress as ought rather to have
been the object of Christian beneficence. But they were quite unsuited to a period in which capital
was borrowed for the extension of enterprise and the employment of labour. The absolute
theological spirit in this, as in other instances, could not admit the modification in rules of conduct
demanded by a new social situation; and vulgar good sense better understood what were the
fundamental conditions of industrial life.
When the intellectual activity previously repressed by the more urgent claims of social
preoccupations tended to revive towards the close of the mediaeval period, the want of a rational
appreciation of the whole of human affairs was felt, and was temporarily met by the adoption of the
results of the best Greek speculation. Hence we find in the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas the
political and economic doctrines of Aristotle reproduced with a partial infusion of Christian elements.
His adherence to his master's point of view is strikingly shown by the fact that he accepts (at least if
he is the author of the De Regimine Principum)(2) the Aristotelian theory of slavery, though by the
action of the forces of his own time the last relics of that institution were being eliminated from
European society.
This great change -- the enfranchisement of the working classes -- was the most important practical
outcome of the Middle Ages. The first step in this movement was the transformation of slavery,
properly so called, into serfdom. The latter was, by its nature, a transitory condition. The serf was
bound to the soil, had fixed domestic relations, and participated in the religious life of the society;
and the tendency of all his circumstances, as well as of the opinions and sentiments of the time,
was in the direction of liberation. This issue was, indeed, not so speedily reached by the rural as by
the urban workman. Already in the second phase serfdom is abolished in the cities and towns,
whilst agricultural serfdom does not anywhere disappear before the third. The latter revolution is
attributed by Adam Smith to the operation of selfish interests, that of the proprietor on the one hand,
who discovered the superior productiveness of cultivation by free tenants, and that of the sovereign
on the other, who, jealous of the great lords, encouraged the encroachments of the villeins on their
authority. But that the Church deserves a share of the merit seems beyond doubt -- moral impulses,
as often happens, conspiring with political and economic motives. The serfs were treated best on
the ecclesiastical estates, and the members of the priesthood, both by their doctrine and by their
situation since the Northern conquests, were constituted patrons and guardians of the oppressed or
subject classes.
Out of the liberation of the serfs rose the first lineaments of the hierarchical constitution of modern
industry in the separation between the entrepreneurs and the workers. The personal
enfranchisement of the latter, stimulating activity and developing initiative, led to accumulations,
which were further promoted by the establishment of order and good government by the civic
corporations which grew out of the enfranchisement. Thus an active capitalist class came into
existence. It appeared first in commerce, the inhabitants of the trading cities importing expensive
luxuries from foreign countries, or the improved manufactures of richer communities, for which the
great proprietors gladly exchanged the raw produce of their lands. In performing the office of
carriers, too, between different countries, these cities had an increasing field for commercial
enterprise. At a later period, as Adam Smith has shown, commerce promoted the growth of
manufactures, which were either produced for foreign sale, or made from foreign materials, or
imitated from the work of foreign artificers. But the first important development of handicrafts in
modern Europe belongs to the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, and the rise of manufacturing
entrepreneurs is not conspicuous within the Middle Ages properly so called. Agriculture, of course,
lags behind; though the feudal lords tend to transform themselves into directors of agricultural
enterprise, their habits and prejudices retard such a movement, and the advance of rural industry
proceeds slowly. It does, however, proceed, partly by the stimulation arising from the desire to
procure the finer objects of manufacture imported from abroad or produced by increased skill at
home, partly by the expenditure on the land of capital amassed in the prosecution of urban
industries.
Some of the trade corporations in the cities appear to have been of great antiquity,. but it was in the
thirteenth century that they rose to importance by being legally recognised and regulated. These
corporations have been much too absolutely condemned by most of the economists, who insist on
applying to the Middle Ages the ideas of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. They were, it is
true, unfitted for modern times, and it was necessary that they should disappear; their existence
indeed was quite unduly prolonged. But they were at first in several respects highly beneficial. They
were a valuable rallying-point for the new industrial forces, which were strengthened by the rise of
the esprit de corps which they fostered. They improved technical skill by the precautions which were
taken for the solidity and finished execution of the wares produced in each locality, and it was with a
view to the advancement of the industrial arts that St. Louis undertook the better organization of the
trades of Paris. The corporations also encouraged good moral habits through the sort of
spontaneous surveillance which they exercised, and they tended to develop the social sentiment
within the limits of each profession, in times when a larger public spirit could scarcely yet be looked
for.(3)
Notes:
1. Roscher, Geschichte der N.O. in Deutschland, pp. 5, sqq.
2. On this question see Jourdain, Philosophie de S. Thomas, vol. 1, pp. 141-9, and 400.
3. Further information on the Economic Literature of the Middle Ages will be found in H. Contzen,
Geschichte der Volkswirthschaftlichen Literatur in Mittelalter (2d ed. 1872), and V. Cusumano, Dell'
Economia Politica nel Medio-evo (1876). See also W. J. Ashley, Introduction to English Economic
History and Theory (1888), vol. i, chap. iii.
Chapter 4
Modern Times: First and Second Phases
The close of the Middle Ages, as Comte has shown, must be placed at the end, not of the fifteenth
but of the thirteenth century. The modern period, which then began, is filled by a development
exhibiting three successive phases, and issuing in the state of things which characterises our own
epoch.
I. During the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries the Catholico-feudal system was breaking down by
the mutual conflicts of its own official members, whilst the constituent elements of a new order were
rising beneath it. On the practical side the antagonists matched against each other were the crown
and the feudal chiefs; and these rival powers sought to strengthen themselves by forming alliances
with the towns and the industrial forces they represented. The movements of this phase can
scarcely be said to find an echo in any contemporary economic literature.
II. In the second phase of the modern period, which opens with the beginning of the sixteenth
century, the spontaneous collapse of the medieval structure is followed by a series of systematic
assaults which still further disorganize it. During this phase the central temporal power, which has
made a great advance in stability and resources, lays hold of the rising elements of manufactures
and commerce, and seeks, whilst satisfying the popular enthusiasm for their promotion, to use them
for political ends, and make them subserve its own strength and splendour by furnishing the
treasure necessary for military success. With this practical effort, and the social tendencies on which
it rests, the Mercantile school of political economy, which then obtains a spontaneous ascendency,
is in close relation. Whilst partially succeeding in the policy we have indicated, the European
Governments yet on the whole necessarily fail, their origin and nature disqualifying them for the task
of guiding the industrial movement; and the discredit of the spiritual power, with which most of them
are confederate, further weakens and undermines them.
III. In the last phase, which coincides approximately with the eighteenth century, the tendency to a
completely new system, both temporal and spiritual, becomes decisively pronounced, first in the
philosophy and general literature of the period, and then in the great French explosion. The
universal critical doctrine, which had been announced by the Protestantism of the previous phase,
and systematised in England towards the close of that phase, is propagated and popularised,
especially by French writers. The spirit of individualism inherent in the doctrine was eminently
adapted to the wants of the time, and the general favour with which the dogmas of the social
contract and laisser faire were received indicated a just sentiment of the conditions proper to the
contemporary situation of European societies. So long as a new coherent system of thought and life
could not be introduced, what was to be desired was a large and active development of personal
energy under no further control of the old social powers than would suffice to prevent anarchy.
Governments were therefore rightly called on to abandon any effective direction of the social
movement, and, as far as possible, to restrict their intervention to the maintenance of material order.
This policy was, from its nature, of temporary application only; but the negative school, according to
its ordinary spirit, erected what was merely a transitory and exceptional necessity into a permanent
and normal law. The unanimous European movement towards the liberation of effort, which
sometimes rose to the height of a public passion, had various sides, corresponding to the different
aspects of thought and life; and of the economic side the French physiocrats were the first theoretic
representatives on the large scale, though the office they undertook was, both in its destructive and
organic provinces, more thoroughly and effectively done by Adam Smith, who ought to be regarded
as continuing and completing their work.
It must be admitted that with the whole modern movement serious moral evils were almost
necessarily connected. The general discipline which the Middle Ages had sought to institute and
had partially succeeded in establishing, though on precarious bases, having broken down, the
sentiment of duty was weakened along with the spirit of ensemble which is its natural ally, and
individualism in doctrine tended to encourage egoism in action. In the economic field this result is
specially conspicuous. National selfishness and private cupidity increasingly dominate; and the
higher and lower industrial classes tend to separation and even to mutual hostility. The new
elements -- science and industry -- which were gradually acquiring ascendency bore indeed in their
bosom an ultimate discipline more efficacious and stable than that which had been dissolved; but
the final synthesis was long too remote, and too indeterminate in its nature, to be seen through the
dispersive and seemingly incoherent growth of those elements. Now, however, that synthesis is
becoming appreciable; and it is the effort towards it, and towards the practical system to be founded
on it, that gives its peculiar character to the period in which we live. And to this spontaneous nisus of
society corresponds, as we shall see, a new form of economic doctrine, in which it tends to be
absorbed into general sociology and subordinated to morals.
It will be the object of the following pages to verify and illustrate in detail the scheme here broadly
indicated, and to point out the manner in which the respective features of the several successive
modern phases find their counterpart and reflection in the historical development of economic
speculation.
FIRST MODERN PHASE
The first phase was marked, on the one hand, by the spontaneous decomposition of the medieval
system, and, on the other, by the rise of several important elements of the new order. The spiritual
power became less apt as well as less able to fulfil its moral office, and the social movement was
more and more left to the irregular impulses of individual energy, often enlisted in the service of
ambition and cupidity. Strong Governments were formed, which served to maintain material order
amidst the growing intellectual and moral disorder. The universal admission of the commons as an
element in the political system showed the growing strength of the industrial forces, as did also in
another way the insurrections of the working classes. The decisive prevalence of peaceful activity
was indicated by the rise of the institution of paid armies -- at first temporary, afterwards permanent
-- which prevented the interruption or distraction of labour by devoting a determinate minority of the
population to martial operations and exercises. Manufactures became increasingly important; and in
this branch of industry the distinction between the entrepreneur and the workers was first firmly
established, whilst fixed relations between these were made possible by the restriction of military
training and service to a special profession. Navigation was facilitated by the use of the mariner's
compass. The art of printing showed how the intellectual movement and the industrial development
were destined to be brought into relation with each other and to work towards common ends. Public
credit rose in Florence, Venice, and Genoa long before Holland and England attained any great
financial importance. Just at the close of the phase, the discovery of America and of the new route
to the East, whilst revolutionising the course of trade, prepared the way for the establishment of
colonies, which contributed powerfully to the growing preponderance of industrial life, and pointed to
its ultimate universality.
It is doubtless due to the equivocal nature of this stage, standing between the medieval and the fully
characterised modern period, that on the theoretic side we find nothing corresponding to such
marvellous practical ferment and expansion. The general political doctrine of Aquinas was retained,
with merely subordinate modifications. The only special economic question which seems to have
received particular attention was that of the nature and functions of money, the importance of which
began to be felt as payments in service or in kind were discontinued, and regular systems of
taxation began to be introduced.
Roscher(1) and after him Wolowski, have called attention, to Nicole Oresme, who was teacher of
Charles V, King of France, and died Bishop of Lisieux in 1382. Roscher pronounces him a great
economist.(2) His Tractatus de Origine, Natura, Jure, et Mutationibus Monetarum (reprinted by
Wolowski, 1864) contains a theory of money which is almost entirely correct according to the views
of the nineteenth century, and is stated with such brevity, clearness, and simplicity of language as
show the work to be from the hand of a master.
SECOND MODERN PHASE: MERCANTILE SYSTEM
Throughout the first modern phase the rise of the new social forces had been essentially
spontaneous; in the second they became the object of systematic encouragement on the part of
Governments, which, now that the financial methods of the Middle Ages no longer sufficed, could
not further their military and political ends by any other means than increased taxation, implying
augmented wealth of the community. Industry thus became a permanent interest of European
Governments, and even tended to become the principal object of their policy. In natural harmony
with this state of facts, the mercantile system arose and grew, attaining its highest development
about the middle of the seventeenth century.
The Mercantile doctrine, stated in its most extreme form, makes wealth and money identical, and
regards it therefore as the great object of a community so to conduct its dealings with other nations
as to attract to itself the largest possible share of the precious metals. Each country must seek to
export the utmost possible quantity of its own manufactures and to import as little as possible of
those of other countries, receiving the difference of the two values in gold and silver. This difference
is called the balance of trade, and the balance is favourable when more money is received than is
paid. Governments must resort to all available expedients -- prohibition of, or high duties on, the
importation of foreign wares, bounties on the export of home manufactures, restrictions on the
export of the precious metals -- for the purpose of securing such a balance.
But this statement of the doctrine, though current in the text-books, does not represent correctly the
views of all who must be classed as belonging to the Mercantile school. Many of the members of
that school were much too clear-sighted to entertain the belief, which the modern student feels
difficulty in supposing any class of thinkers to have professed, that wealth consists exclusively of
gold and silver. The mercantilists may be best described, as Roscher(3) has remarked, not by any
definite economic theorem which they held in common, but by a set of theoretic tendencies,
commonly found in combination, though severally prevailing in different degrees in different minds.
These tendencies may be enumerated as follows: (1) Towards over-estimating the importance of
possessing a large amount of the precious metals; (2) towards an undue exaltation (a) of foreign
trade over domestic, and (b) of the industry which works up materials over that which provides them;
(3) towards attaching too high a value to a dense population as an element of national strength; and
(4) towards invoking the action of the state in furthering artificially the attainment of the several ends
thus proposed as desirable.
If we consider the contemporary position of affairs in Western Europe, we shall have no difficulty in
understanding how these tendencies would inevitably arise. The discoveries in the New World had
led to a large development of the European currencies. The old feudal economy founded principally
on dealings in kind, had given way before the new "money economy," and the dimensions of the
latter were everywhere expanding. Circulation was becoming more rapid, distant communications
more frequent, city life and movable property more important. The mercantilists were impressed by
the fact that money is wealth sui generis, that it is at all times in universal demand, and that it puts
into the hands of its possessor the power of acquiring all other commodities. The period, again, was
marked by the formation of great states, with powerful Governments at their head. These
Governments required men and money for the maintenance of permanent armies, which, especially
for the religious and Italian wars, were kept up on a great scale, Court expenses, too, were more
lavish than ever before, and a larger number of civil officials was employed. The royal domains and
dues were insufficient to meet these requirements, and taxation grew with the demands of the
monarchies. Statesmen saw that for their own political ends industry must flourish. But
manufactures make possible a denser population and a higher total value of exports than
agriculture; they open a less limited and more promptly extensible field to enterprise. Hence they
became the object of special Governmental favour and patronage, whilst agriculture fell
comparatively into the background. The growth of manufactures reacted on commerce, to which a
new and mighty arena had been opened by the establishment of colonies. These were viewed
simply as estates to be worked for the advantage of the mother countries, and the aim of statesmen
was to make the colonial trade a new source of public revenue. Each nation, as a whole, working for
its own power, and the greater ones for predominance, they entered into a competitive struggle in
the economic no less than in the political field, success in the former being indeed, by the rulers,
regarded as instrumental to pre-eminence in the latter. A national economic interest came to exist,
of which the Government made itself the representative head. States became a sort of artificial
hothouses for the rearing of urban industries. Production was subjected to systematic regulation
with the object of securing the goodness and cheapness of the exported articles, and so maintaining
the place of the nation in foreign markets. The industrial control was exercised, in part directly by the
State, but largely also through privileged corporations and trading companies. High duties on
imports were resorted to, at first perhaps mainly for revenue, but afterwards in the interest of
national production., Commercial treaties were a principal object of diplomacy, the end in view being
to exclude the competition of other nations in foreign markets, whilst in the home market as little
room as possible was given for the introduction of anything but raw materials from abroad. The
colonies were prohibited from trading with other European nations than the parent country, to which
they supplied either the precious metals or raw produce purchased with home manufactures. It is
evident that what is known as the Mercantile doctrine was essentially the theoretic counterpart of the
practical activities of the time, and that nations and Governments were led to it, not by any form of
scientific thought, but by the force of outward circumstance, and the observation of facts which lay
on the surface.
And yet, if we regard the question from the highest point of view of philosophic history, we must
pronounce the universal enthusiasm of this second modern phase for manufactures and commerce
to have been essentially just, as leading the nations into the main avenues of general social
development. If the thought of the period, instead of being impelled by contemporary circumstances,
could have been guided by sociological prevision, it must have entered with zeal upon the same
path which it empirically selected. The organization of agricultural industry could not at that period
make any marked progress, for the direction of its operations was still in the hands of the feudal
class, which could not in general really learn the habits of industrial life, or place itself in sufficient
harmony with the workers on its domains. The industry of the towns had to precede that of the
country, and the latter had to be developed mainly through the indirect action of the former. And it is
plain that it was in the life of the manufacturing proletariat, whose labours are necessarily the most
continuous and the most social, that a systematic discipline could at a later period be first applied, to
be afterwards extended to the rural populations.
That the efforts of Governments for the furtherance of manufactures and commerce were really
effective towards that end is admitted by Adam Smith, and cannot reasonably be doubted, though
free trade doctrinaires have often denied it. Technical skill must have been promoted by their
encouragements; whilst new forms of national production were fostered by attracting workmen from
other countries, and by lightening the burden of taxation on struggling industries. Communication
and transport by land and sea were more rapidly improved with a view to facilitate traffic; and, not
the least important effect, the social dignity of the industrial professions was enhanced relatively to
that of the classes before exclusively dominant.
It has often been asked to whom the foundation of the mercantile system, in the region whether of
thought or of practice, is to be attributed. But the question admits of no absolute answer. That mode
of conceiving economic facts arises spontaneously in unscientific minds, and ideas suggested by it
are to be found in the Greek and Latin writers. The policy which it dictates was, as we have shown,
inspired by the situation of the European nations at the opening of the modern period. Such a policy
had been already in some degree practised in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, thus preceding
any formal exposition or defence of its speculative basis. At the commencement of the sixteenth
century it began to exercise a widely extended influence. Charles V adopted it, and his example
contributed much to its predominance. Henry VIII and Elizabeth conformed their measures to it. The
leading states soon entered on a universal competition, in which each Power brought into play all its
political and financial resources for the purpose of securing to itself manufacturing and commercial
preponderance. Through almost the whole of the seventeenth century the prize, so far as commerce
was concerned, remained in the possession of Holland, Italy having lost her former ascendency by
the opening of the new maritime routes, and by her political misfortunes, and Spain and Germany
being depressed by protracted wars and internal dissensions. The admiring envy of Holland felt by
English politicians and economists appears in such writers as Raleigh, Mun, Child, and Temple;(4)
and how strongly the same spectacle acted on French policy is shown by a well-known letter of
Colbert to M. de Pomponne,(5) ambassador to the Dutch States. Cromwell, by the Navigation Act,
which destroyed the carrying trade of Holland and founded the English empire of the sea, and
Colbert, by his whole economic policy, domestic and international, were the chief practical
representatives of the mercantile system. From the latter great statesman the Italian publicist
Mengotti gave to that system the name of Colbertismo; but it would be an error to consider the
French minister as having absolutely accepted its dogmas. He regarded his measures as temporary
only, and spoke of protective duties as crutches by the help of which manufacturers might learn to
walk and then throw them away. The policy of exclusions had been previously pursued by Sully,
partly with a view to the accumulation of a royal treasure, but chiefly from his special enthusiasm for
agriculture, and his dislike of the introduction of foreign luxuries as detrimental to the national
character. Colbert's tariff of 1664 not merely simplified but considerably reduced the existing duties;
the tariff of 1667 indeed increased them, but that was really a political measure directed against the
Dutch. It seems certain that France owed in a large measure to his policy the vast development of
trade and manufactures which so much impressed the imagination of contemporary Europe, and of
which we hear so much from English writers of the time of Petty. But this policy had also undeniably
its dark side. Industry was forced by such systematic regulation to follow invariable courses, instead
of adapting itself to changing tastes and popular demand. Nor was it free to simplify the processes
of production, or to introduce increased division of labour and improved appliances. Spontaneity,
initiation, and invention were repressed or discouraged, and thus ulterior sacrificed in a great
measure to immediate results. The more enlightened statesmen, and Colbert in particular,
endeavoured, it is true, to minimise these disadvantages by procuring, often at great expense, and
communicating to the trades through inspectors nominated by the Government, information
respecting improved processes employed elsewhere in the several arts; but this, though in some
degree a real, was certainly on the whole, and in the long run, an insufficient compensation.
We must not expect from the writers of this stage any exposition of political economy as a whole;
the publications which appeared were for the most part evoked by special exigencies, and related to
particular questions, usually of a practical kind, which arose out of the great movements of the time.
They were in fact of the nature of counsels to the Governments of states, pointing out how best they
might develop the productive powers at their disposal and increase the resources of their respective
countries. They are conceived (as List claims for them) strictly in the spirit of national economy, and
cosmopolitanism is essentially foreign to them. On these monographs the mercantile theory
sometimes had little influence, the problems discussed not involving its tenets. But it must in most
cases be taken to be the scheme of fundamental doctrine (so far as it was ever entitled to such a
description) which in the last resort underlies the writer's conclusions.
The rise of prices following on the discovery of the American mines was one of the subjects which
first attracted the attention of theorists. This rise brought about a great and gradually increasing
disturbance of existing economic relations, and so produced much perplexity and anxiety, which
were all the more felt because the cause of the change was not understood. To this was added the
loss and inconvenience arising from the debasement of the currency often resorted to by sovereigns
as well as by republican states. Italy suffered most from this latter abuse, which was multiplied by
her political divisions. It was this evil which called forth the work of Count Gasparo Scaruffi
(Discorso sopra le monete e della vera proporzione fra l'oro e l'argento, 1582). In this he put forward
the bold idea of a universal money, everywhere identical in size, shape, composition, and
designation. The project was, of course, premature, and was not adopted even by the Italian princes
to whom the author specially appealed; but the reform is one which, doubtless, the future will see
realised. Gian Donato Turbolo, master of the Neapolitan mint, in his Discorsi e Relazioni, 1629,
protested against any tampering with the currency. Another treatise relating to the subject of money
was that of the Florentine Bernardo Davanzati, otherwise known as the able translator of Tacitus,
Lezioni delle Monete, 1588. It is a slight and somewhat superficial production, only remarkable as
written with conciseness and elegance of style.(6)
A French writer who dealt with the question of money, but from a different point of view, was Jean
Bodin. In his ponse aux paradoxes de M. Malestroit touchant l'enchérissement de toutes les
choses et des monnaies, 1568, and in his Discours sur le rehaussement et la diminution des
monnaies, 1578, he showed a more rational appreciation than many of his contemporaries of the
causes of the revolution in prices, and the relation of the variations in money to the market values of
wares in general as well as to the wages of labour. He saw that the amount of money in circulation
did not constitute the wealth of the community, and that the prohibition of the export of the precious
metals was useless, because rendered inoperative by the necessities of trade. Bodin is no
inconsiderable figure in the literary history of the epoch, and did not confine his attention to
economic problems; in his Six livres de la République, about 1576, he studies the general
conditions of the prosperity and stability of states. In harmony with the conditions of his age, he
approves of absolute Governments as the most competent to ensure the security and well-being of
their subjects. He enters into an elaborate defence of individual property against Plato and More,
rather perhaps because the scheme of his work required the treatment of that theme than because it
was practically urgent in his day, when the excesses of the Anabaptists had produced a strong
feeling against communistic doctrines. He is under the general influence of the mercantilist views,
and approves of energetic Governmental interference in industrial matters, of high taxes on foreign
manufactures and low duties on raw materials and articles of food, and attaches great importance to
a dense population. But he is not a blind follower of the system; he wishes for unlimited freedom of
trade in many cases; and he is in advance of his more eminent contemporary Montaigne(7) in
perceiving that the gain of one nation is not necessarily the loss of another. To the public finances,
which he calls the sinews of the State, he devotes much attention, and insists on the duties of the
Government in respect to the right adjustment of taxation. In general he deserves the praise of
steadily keeping in view the higher aims and interests of society in connection with the regulation
and development of its material life.(8)
Correct views as to the cause of the general rise of prices are also put forward by the English writer,
W. S. (William Stafford), in his Briefe Conceipte of English Policy, published in 1581, and dedicated
to Queen Elizabeth. It is in the form of a dialogue, and is written with liveliness and spirit. The author
seems to have been acquainted with the writings of Bodin. He has just ideas as to the nature of
money, and fully understands the evils arising from a debased coinage. He describes in detail the
way in which the several interests in the country had been affected by such debasement in previous
reigns, as well as by the change in the value of the precious metals. The great popular grievance of
his day, the conversion of arable land into pasture, he attributes chiefly to the restrictions on the
export of corn, which he desires to see abolished. But in regard to manufactures he is at the same
point of view with the later mercantilists, and proposes the exclusion of all foreign wares which might
as well be provided at home, and the prohibition of the export of raw materials intended to be
worked up abroad.
Out of the question of money, too, arose the first remarkable German production on political
economy which had an original national character and addressed the public in the native tongue.
The Ernestine Saxon line was inclined (1530) to introduce a debasement of the currency. A
pamphlet, Gemeine Stymmen von der Müntze, was published in opposition to this proceeding,
under the auspices of the Albertine branch, whose policy was sounder in the economic sphere. A
reply appeared justifying the Ernestine project. This was followed by a rejoinder from the Albertine
side. The Ernestine pamphlet is described by Roscher as ill-written, obscure, inflated, and, as might
be expected from the thesis it maintained, sophistical. But it is interesting as containing a statement
of the fundamental principles of the mercantile system more than one hundred years before the
publication of Mun's book, and forty-six before that of Bodin's Six livres de la publique. The
Albertine tracts, according to Roscher, exhibit such sound views of the conditions and evidences of
national wealth, of the nature of money and trade, And of the rights and duties of Governments in
relation to economic action, that he regards the unknown author as entitled to a place beside
Raleigh and the other English "colonial-theorists" of the end of the sixteenth and beginning of the
seventeenth century.
In connection with the same subject of money we meet the great name of Copernicus. His treatise
De monetae cudendae ratione, 1526 (first printed in 1816), was written by order of King Sigismund I,
and is an exposition of the principles on which it was proposed to reform the currency of the
Prussian provinces of Poland. It advocates unity of the monetary system throughout the entire state,
with strict integrity in the quality of the coin, and the charge of a seigniorage sufficient to cover the
expenses of mintage.
Antonio Serra is regarded by some as the creator of modern political economy. He was a native of
Cosenza in Calabria. His Breve Trattato delle cause che possono fare abbondare li regni d'oro e
d'argento dove non sono miniere, 1613, was written during his imprisonment, which is believed to
have been due to his having taken part in the conspiracy of Campanella for the liberation of Naples
from the Spanish yoke and the establishment of a republican Government. This work, long
overlooked, was brought into notice in the following century by Galiani and others. Its title alone
would sufficiently indicate that the author had adopted the principles of the mercantile system, and
in fact in this treatise the essential doctrines of that system are expounded in a tolerably formal and
consecutive manner. He strongly insists on the superiority of manufactures over agriculture as a
source of national wealth, and uses in support of this view the prosperity of Genoa, Florence, and
Venice, as contrasted with the depressed condition of Naples. With larger insight than many of the
mercantilists exhibit, he insists on the importance, towards the acquisition of wealth, not alone of
favourable external conditions, but of energetic character and industrious habits in a population, as
well as of a stable government and a good administration of the laws.
The first systematic treatise on our science which proceeded from a French author was the Traité de
l'Économie Politique, published by Montchrétien de Watteville (or Vasteville)(9) in 1615. The use of
the title, says Roscher, now for the first time given to the science, was in itself an important service,
since even Bacon understood by "Economia" only the theory of domestic management. The general
tendencies and aims of the period are seen in the fact that this treatise, notwithstanding the
comprehensive name it bears, does not deal with agriculture at all, but only with the mechanical
arts, navigation, commerce, and public finance. The author is filled with the then dominant
enthusiasm for foreign trade and colonies. He advocates the control by princes of the industry of
their subjects, and condemns the too great freedom, which, in his opinion to their own detriment, the
Governments of Spain, Portugal, and Holland had given to trade. His book may be regarded as a
formal exposition of the principles of the mercantile system for the use of Frenchmen.
A similar office was performed in England by Thomas Mun. In his two works, A Discourse of Trade
from England unto the East Indies, 2nd ed., 1621, and especially in England's Treasure by Foreign
Trade, 1664 (posthumous), we have for the first time a clear and systematic statement of the theory
of the balance of trade, as well as of the means by which, according to the author's view, a
favourable balance could be secured for England. The great object of the economic policy of a
state, according to him, should be so to manage its export of manufactures, its direct and carrying
trade, and its customs duties, as to attract to itself money from abroad. He was, however, opposed
to the prohibition of the export of the precious metals in exchange for foreign wares, but on the
ground, fully according with his general principles, that those wares might afterwards be re-exported
and might then bring back more treasure than had been originally expended in their purchase; the
first export of money might be, as he said, the seed-time, of which the ultimate receipt of a larger
amount would be the harvest.(10) He saw, too, that it is inexpedient to have too much money
circulating in a country, as this enhances the prices of commodities, and so makes them less
saleable to foreigners, but he is favourable to the formation and maintenance of a state treasure.
(11)
One of the most remarkable of the moderate mercantilists was Sir Josiah Child (Brief Observations
concerning Trade and the interest of Money, 1668, and A New Discourse of Trade, 1668 and 1790).
He was one of those who held up Holland as a model for the imitation of his fellow-countrymen. He
is strongly impressed with the importance for national wealth and well-being of a low rate of interest,
which he says is to commerce and agriculture what the soul is to the body, and which he held to be
the "cauza causans of all the other causes of the riches of the Dutch people." Instead of regarding
such low rate as dependent on determinate conditions, which should be allowed to evolve
themselves spontaneously, he thinks it should be created and maintained by public authority. Child,
whilst adhering to the doctrine of the balance of trade, observes that a people cannot always sell to
foreigners without ever buying from them, and denies that the export of the precious metals is
necessarily detrimental. He has the ordinary mercantilist partiality for a numerous population. He
advocates the reservation by the Mother Country of the sole right of trade with her colonies, and,
under certain limitations, the formation of privileged trading companies. As to the Navigation Act, he
takes up a position not unlike that afterwards occupied by Adam Smith, regarding that measure
much more favourably from the political than from the economic point of view. It will be seen that he
is somewhat eclectic in his opinions; but he cannot properly be regarded, though some have
attributed to him that character, as a precursor of the free-trade school of the eighteenth century.
Two other eclectics may be here mentioned, in whom just views are mingled with mercantilist
prejudices -- Sir William Temple and Charles Davenant. The former in his Observations upon the
United Province of the Netherlands, 1672, and his Essay on the Trade of Ireland, 1673, has many
excellent remarks on fundamental economic principles, as on the functions of labour and of saving
in the production of national wealth; but he is infected with the errors of the theory of the balance of
trade. He follows the lead of Raleigh and Child in urging his fellow-countrymen to imitate the
example of the Dutch in their economic policy -- advice which in his case was founded on his
observations during a lengthened residence in Holland as ambassador to the States. Davenant in
his Essay on the East India Trade, 1696-97, Essay on the Probable Ways of making the People
Gainers in the Balance of Trade, 1699, etc., also takes up an eclectic position, combining some
correct views on wealth and money with mercantilist notions on trade, and recommending
Governmental restrictions on colonial commerce as strongly as he advocates freedom of exchange
at home.
Whilst the mercantile system represented the prevalent form of economic thought in the
seventeenth century, and was alone dominant in the region of practical statesmanship, there was
growing up, side by side with it, a body of opinion, different and indeed hostile in character, which
was destined ultimately to drive it from the field. The new ideas were first developed in England,
though it was in France that in the following century they took hold of the public mind, and became a
power in politics. That they should first show themselves here, and afterwards be extended, applied,
and propagated throughout Europe by French writers, belongs to the order of things according to
which the general negative doctrine in morals and politics, undoubtedly of English origin, found its
chief home in France, and was thence diffused in widening circles through the civilized world. In
England this movement of economic thought took the shape mainly of individual criticism of the
prevalent doctrines, founded on a truer analysis of facts and conceptions; in France it was
penetrated with a powerful social sentiment, furnished the creed of a party, and inspired a protest
against existing institutions and an urgent demand for practical reform.
Regarded from the theoretic side, the characteristic features of the new direction were the following.
The view of at least the extreme mercantilists that national wealth depends on the accumulation of
the precious metals is proved to be false, and the gifts of nature and the labour of man are shown to
be its real sources. The exaggerated estimate of the importance of foreign commerce is reduced,
and attention is once more turned to agriculture and the conditions of its successful prosecution. On
the side of practical policy, a so-called favourable balance of trade is seen not to be the true object
of a nation's or a statesman's efforts, but the procuring for the whole population in the fullest
measure the enjoyment of the necessaries and conveniences of life. And -- what more than
anything else contrasts the new system with the old -- the elaborate apparatus of prohibitions,
protective duties, bounties, monopolies, and privileged corporations, which the European
Governments had created in the supposed interests of manufactures and trade, is denounced or
deprecated as more an impediment than a furtherance, and the freedom of industry is insisted on as
the one thing needful. This circle of ideas, of course, emerges only gradually, and its earliest
representatives in economic literature in general apprehend it imperfectly and advocate it with
reserve; but it rises steadily in importance, being more and more favoured by the highest minds, and
finding an increasing body of supporters amongst the intelligent public.
Some occasional traits of an economic scheme in harmony with these new tendencies are to be
found in the De Cive and Leviathan of Hobbes. But the efficacy of that great thinker lay rather in the
general philosophic field; and by systematising, for the first time, the whole negative doctrine, he
gave a powerful impulse towards the demolition of the existing social order, which was destined, as
we shall see, to have momentous consequences in the economic no less than in the strictly political
department of things.
A writer of no such extended range, but of much sagacity and good sense, was Sir William Petty,
author of a number of pieces containing germs of a sound economic doctrine. A leading thought in
his writings is that "labour is the father and active principle of wealth, lands are the mother." He
divides a population into two classes, the productive and the unproductive, according as they are or
are not occupied in producing useful material things. The value of any commodity depends, he says,
anticipating Ricardo, on the amount of labour necessary for its production. He is desirous of
obtaining a universal measure of value, and chooses as his unit the average food of the cheapest
kind required for a man's daily sustenance. He understands the nature of the rent of land as the
excess of the price of its produce over the cost of production. He disapproves of the attempt to fix by
authority a maximum rate of interest, and is generally opposed to Governmental interference with
the course of industry. He sees that a country requires for its exchanges a definite quantity of money
and may have too much of it, and condemns the prohibition of its exportation. He holds that one only
of the precious metals must be the foundation of the currency, the other circulating as an ordinary
article of merchandise. Petty's name is specially associated with the progress of statistics, with
which he was much occupied, and which he called by the name of political arithmetic. Relying on
the results of such inquiries, he set himself strongly against the opinion which was maintained by
the author of Britannia Languens (1680), Fortrey, Roger Coke, and other writers, that the prosperity
of England was on the decline.
The most thoroughgoing and emphatic assertion of the free-trade doctrine against the system of
prohibitions, which had gained strength by the Revolution, was contained in Sir Dudley North's
Discourses upon Trade, 1691. He shows that wealth may exist independently of gold or silver, its
source being human industry, applied either to the cultivation of the soil or to manufactures. The
precious metals, however, are one element of national wealth, and perform highly important offices.
Money may exist in excess, as well as in defect, in a country; and the quantity of it required for the
purposes of trade will vary with circumstances; its ebb and flow will regulate themselves
spontaneously. It is a mistake to suppose that stagnation of trade arises from want of money; it must
arise either from a glut of the home market, or from a disturbance of foreign commerce, or from
diminished consumption caused by poverty. The export of money in the course of traffic, instead of
diminishing, increases the national wealth, trade being only an exchange of superfluities. Nations
are economically related to the world just in the same way as cities to the state or as families to the
city. North emphasises more than his predecessors the value of the home trade. With respect to the
interest of capital, he maintains that it depends, the the price of any commodity, on the proportion of
demand and supply, and that a low rate is a result of the relative increase of capital, and cannot be
brought about by arbitrary regulations, as had been proposed by Child and others. In arguing the
question of free trade, he urges that individuals often take their private interest as the measure of
good and evil, and would for its sake debar others from their equal right of buying and selling, but
that every advantage given to one interest or branch of trade over another is injurious to the public.
No trade is unprofitable to the public; if it were, it would be given up; when trades thrive, so does the
public, of which they form a part. Prices must determine themselves, and cannot be fixed by law;
and all forcible interference with them does harm instead of good. No people can become rich by
state regulations, -- only by peace, industry, freedom, and unimpeded economic activity. It will be
seen how closely North's view of things approaches to that embodied some eighty years later in
Adam Smith's great work.(12)
Locke is represented by Roscher as, along with Petty and North, making up the "triumvirate" of
eminent British economists of this period who laid the foundations of a new and more rational
doctrine than that of the mercantilists. But this view of his claims seems capable of being accepted
only with considerable deductions. His specially economic writings are Considerations of the
lowering of Interest and raising the value of Money, 1691, and Further Considerations, 1695.
Though Leibnitz declared with respect to these treatises that nothing more solid or intelligent could
be said on their subject, it is difficult absolutely to adopt that verdict. Locke's spirit of sober
observation and patient analysis led him indeed to some just conclusions; and he is entitled to the
credit of having energetically resisted the debasement of the currency, which was then
recommended by some who were held to be eminent practical authorities. But he falls into errors
which show that he had not by any means completely emancipated himself from the ideas of the
mercantile system. He attaches far too much importance to money as such. He says expressly that
riches consist in a plenty of gold and silver, that is, as he explains, in having more in proportion of
those metals than the rest of the world or than our neighbours. "In a country not furnished with
mines, there are but two ways of growing rich, either conquest or commerce." Hence he accepts the
doctrine of the balance of trade. He shows that the rate of interest can no more be fixed by law than
the rent of houses or the hire of ships, and opposes Child's demand for legislative interference with
it. But he erroneously attributed the fall of the rate which had taken place generally in Europe to the
increase of the quantity of gold and silver by the discovery of the American mines. He sets too
absolute a value on a numerous population, in this point agreeing with Petty. On wages he observes
that the rate must be such as to cover the indispensable wants of the labourer; when the price of
subsistence rises, wages must rise in a like ratio, or the working population must come on the poor
rates. The fall of the rent of land he regards as a sure sign of the decline of national wealth. "Taxes,
however contrived, and out of whose hands soever immediately taken, do, in a country where their
great fund is in land, for the most part terminate upon land." In this last proposition we see a
foreshadowing of the impôt unique of the physiocrats. Whatever may have been Locke's direct
economic services, his principal importance, like that of Hobbes, lies in his general philosophic and
political principles, which powerfully affected French and indeed European thought, exciting a spirit
of opposition to arbitrary power, and laying the foundation of the doctrine developed in the Contrat
Social.(13)
Notes:
1. Comptes rendus de l'Académie des Sciences morales et politiques, lxii, 435, sqq.
2. Geschichte der N.O. in Deutschland, p. 25.
3. Geschichte der N.O. in Deutschland, p. 228, sqq.
4. Roscher, Geschichte der N.O. in Deutschland, p. 227.
5. Clément, Histoire de la vie et de l'administration de Colbert (1846), p. 134.
6. A more valuable work is that of Romeo Bocchi (written in 1611 and published in 1621), Della
guista universale misura e suo typo: vol. i, Anima della Moneta; vol. ii, Corpo della Moneta, of which
a full account has been given by U. Gobbi in his Economia Politica negli Scrittori Italiani del Secolo
xvi-xvii (1889).
7. "Il ne se faict aucun profit qu'au dommage d'autruy." Essais. liv. I, chap. 21.
8. A writer whose literary activity was of a similar character to Bodin's and who seems to have been
much influenced by him, was the Italian Giovanni Botero (1540-1617). His treatise Delle cause della
grandezza delle citta (1588; Eng. Trans. by Robert Peterson, 1606) was introductory to his chief
work Della ragion di Stato, libri X (1589), in which he combated the principles of Machiavelli.
9. Montchrétien, having fomented the rebellion in Normandy in 1621, was slain with a few followers,
by Claude Turgot, lord of Les Tourailles, who belonged to the elder branch of the noble house from
which the great Turgot was descended.
10. On Mun's doctrines, see Smith's Wealth of Nations, Bk. iv. chap. i.
11. Writers of less importance who followed the same direction were Sir Thomas Culpeper (A Tract
against the High Rate of Usury, 1623, and Useful Remark on High Interest 1641), Sir Dudley Digges
(Defence of Trade, 1615), G. Malynes (Consuetude vel Lex Mercatoria, 1622) E. Misselden (Circle
of Commerce, 1623), Samuel Fortrey (England's Interest and Improvement, 1663 and 1673), and
John Pollexien (England and India inconsistent in their Manufacturers, 1697).
12. Yet M. Eugène Daire asserts (Oeuvres de Turgot, i, 322) that "Hume et Tucker sont les deux
premiers écrivains qui se soinet élevés, en Angleterre, au-dessus des theéories du système
mercantile."
13. Minor English writers who followed the new economic direction were Lewis Roberts, Treasure of
Traffick, 1641; Rice Vaughan, Discourse of Coin and Coinage, 16715; Nicholas Barbon, Discourse
concerning Coining the new money higher, 1696, in which some of Locke's errors were pointed out;
and the author of an anonymous book entitled Considerations on the East India Trade, 1701.
Practical questions much debated at this period were those connected with banking, on which a
lengthened controversy took place, S. Lamb, W. Potter, F. Cradocke, M. Lewis. M. Godfrey, R.
Murray, H. Chamberlain, and W. Paterson, founder of the Bank of England (1694), producing many
pamphlets on the subject; and the management of the poor, which was treated by Locke, Sir
Matthew Hale, R. Haines, T. Firmin, and others.
Chapter 5
Third Modern Phase: System of Natural Liberty
The changes introduced during the third phase in the internal organisation of the industrial world
were (1) the more complete separation of banking from general commerce, and the wider extension
of its operations, especially through the system of public credit; and (2) the great development of the
use of machinery in production. The latter did not become very prominent during the first half of the
eighteenth century, Whilst tending to promote the dignity of the working classes by relieving them
from degrading and exhausting forms of labour, it widened the gulf between them and the capitalist
employers. It thus became plain that for the definitive constitution of industry a moral reform was the
necessary preliminary condition.
With respect to the political relations of industry, a remarkable inversion now showed itself. The
systematic encouragements which the European Governments had extended to it in the preceding
phase had been prompted by their desire to use it as an instrument for achieving the military
superiority which was the great end of thek policy. Now, on the contrary, the military spirit
subordinated itself to the industrial, and the armies and the diplomacy of Governments were placed
at the service of commerce. The wars which filled a large part of the eighteenth century were
essentially Commercial wars, arising out of the effort to sustain or extend the colonial
establishments founded in the previous phase, or to deprive rival nations of the industrial
advantages connected with the possession of such establishments. This change of attitude,
notwithstanding its deplorable tendency to foster international enmities and jealousies, marked a
real and important progress by pointing to industrial activity as the one permanent practical
destination of modern societies.
But, whilst by this sort of action furthering the ascendency of the new forces, the ruling powers, both
in England and France, betrayed the alarm they felt at the subversive tendencies which appeared
inherent in the modern movement by taking up in their domestic policy an attitude of resistance.
Reaction became triumphant in France during the latter half of the reign of Louis XIV, under the
disastrous influence of Madame de Maintenon. In England, after the transaction of 1688, by which
the Government was consolidated on the double basis of aristocratic power and official orthodoxy,
the state policy became not so much retrograde as stationary, industrial conquest being put forward
to satisfy the middle class and wean it from the pursuit of a social renovation. In both countries there
was for some time a noticeable check in the intellectual development, and Roscher and others have
observed that, in economic studies particularly, the first three decades of the eighteenth century
were a period of general stagnation, eclecticism for the most part taking the place of originality. The
movement was, however, soon to be resumed, but with an altered and more formidable character.
The negative doctrine, which had risen and taken a definite form in England, was diffused and
popularised in France, where it became evident, even before the decisive explosion, that the only
possible issue lay in a radical social transformation. The partial schools of Voltaire and Rousseau in
different ways led up to a violent crisis, whilst taking little thought of the conditions of a system which
could replace the old; but the more complete and organic school, of which Diderot is the best
representative, looked through freedom to a thorough reorganisation. Its constructive aim is shown
by the design of the Encyclopédie -- a project, however, which could have only a temporary
success, because no real synthesis was forthcoming, and this joint production of minds often
divergent could possess no more than an external unity. It was with this great school that the
physiocrats were specially connected; and, in common with its other members whilst pushing
towards an entire change of the existing system, they yet would gladly have avoided political
demolition through the exercise of a royal dictatorship, or contemplated it only as the necessary
condition of a new and better order of things. But, though marked off by such tendencies from the
purely revolutionary sects, their method and fundamental ideas were negative, resting, as they did,
essentially on the basis of the jus natura. We shall follow in detail these French developments in
their special relation to economic science, and afterwards notice the corresponding movements in
other European countries which showed themselves before the appearance of Adam Smith, or were
at least unaffected by his influence.
BEFORE ADAM SMITH
France
The more liberal, as well as more rational, principles put forward by the English thinkers of the new
type began, early in the eighteenth century, to find an echo in France, where the clearer and more
vigorous intellects were prepared for their reception by a sense of the great evils which exaggerated
mercantilism, serving as instrument of political ambition, had produced in that country. The
impoverished condition of the agricultural population, the oppressive weight and unequal imposition
of taxation, and the unsound state of the public finances had produced a general feeling of disquiet,
and led several distinguished writers to protest strongly against the policy of Colbert and to demand
a complete reform.
The most important amongst them was Pierre Boisguillebert (d. 1714), whose whole life was
devoted to these controversies. In his statistical writings (Détail de la France sous le règne présent,
1697; Factum de la France, 1707), he brings out in gloomy colours the dark side of the age of Louis
XIV, and in his theoretic works (Traité de la nature et du commerce des grains; Dissertations sur la
nature des reichesses de l'argent et des tributs; and Essai sur la rareté de l'argent) he appears as
an earnest, even passionate, antagonist of the mercantile school. He insists again and again on the
fact that national wealth does not consist in gold and silver, but in useful things, foremost among
which are the products of agriculture. He even goes so far as to speak of "argent criminel," which
from being the slave of trade, as it ought to be, had become its tyrant. He sets the "genuinely French
Sully" far above the "Italianising Colbert," and condemns all arbitrary regulations affecting either
foreign or internal commerce, especially as regards the corn trade. National wealth does not depend
on Governments, whose interference does more harm than good; the natural laws of the economic
order of things cannot be violated or neglected with impunity; the interests ot the several classes of
society in a system of freedom are identical, and those of individuals coincide with that of the state.
A similar solidarity exists between different nations; in their economic dealings they are related to
the world as individual towns to a nation, and not merely plenty, but peace and harmony, will result
from their unfettered intercourse. Men he divides into two classes -- those who do nothing and enjoy
everything, and those who labour from morning to night often without earning a bare subsistence;
the latter he would favour in every way. Here we catch the breath of popular sympathy which fills the
social atmosphere of the eighteenth century. He dwells with special emphasis on the claims of
agriculture, which had in France fallen into unmerited neglect, and with a view to its improvement
calls for a reform in taxation. He would replace indirect taxes by taxes on income, and would restore
the payment of taxes in kind, with the object of securing equality of burden and eliminating every
element of the arbitrary. He has some interesting views of a general character: thus he
approximates to a correct conception of agricultural rent, and he points to the order in which human
wants follow each other -- those of necessity, convenience, comfort, superfluity, and ostentation
succeeding in the order named, and ceasing in the inverse order to be felt as wealth decreases. The
depreciating tone in which Voltaire speaks of Boisguillebert (Siècle de Louis XIV, chap 30) is
certainly not justified; he had a great economic talent, and his writings contain important germs of
truth. But he appears to have exerted little influence, theoretical or practical, in his own time.
The same general line of thought was followed by Marshal de Vauban (1633-1707) in his economic
tracts, especially that bearing the title of Projet d'une dixme Royale, 1707, which was suppressed by
the authorities, and lost for him the favour of his sovereign, but has added lustre to his name in the
judgment of posterity. He is deeply impressed with the deplorable condition of the working classes
of France in his day. He urges that the aim of the Government should be the welfare of all orders of
the community; that all are entitled to like favour and furtherance; that the often despised and
wronged lower class is the basis of the social organisation; that labour is the foundation of all
wealth, and agriculture the most important species of labour; that the most essential condition of
successful industry is freedom; and that all unnecessary or excessive restrictions on manufactures
and commerce should be swept away. He protests in particular against the inequalities of taxation,
and the exemptions and privileges enjoyed by the higher ranks. With the exception of some duties
on consumption he would abolish all the existing taxes, and substitute for them a single tax on
income and land, impartially applied to all classes, which he describes under the name of "Dixme
Royale," that is to say, a tenth in kind of all agricultural produce, and a tenth of money income
chargeable on manufacturers and traders.(1)
The liberal and humane spirit of Fénelon led him to aspire after freedom of commerce with foreign
nations, and to preach the doctrine that the true superiority of one state over another lies in the
number indeed, but also in the morality, intelligence, and industrious habits of its population, The
Télémaque, in which these views were presented in an attractive form, was welcomed and read
amongst all ranks and classes, and was thus an effective organ for the propagation of opinion.
After these witers there is a marked blank in the field of French economic thought, broken only by
the Réflexions Politiques sur les Finances et le Commerce 19738) of Dutot, a pupil of Law, and the
semi-mercantilist Essais Politiques sure le Commerce (1731) of Mélon, till we come to the great
name of Montesquieu. The Esprit des Lois (1748), so far as it deals with economic subjects, is
written upon the whole from a point of view adverse to the mercantile system, especially in his
treatment of money, though in his observations on colonies and elsewhere he falls in with the ideas
of that system. His immortal service, however, was not rendered by any special research, but by his
enforcement of the doctrine of natural laws regulating social no less than physical phenomena.
There is no other thinker of importance on economic subjects in France till the appearance of the
physiocrats, which marks an epoch in the history of the science.
The heads of the physiocratic school were François Quesnay (1694-1774) and Jean Claude Marie
Vincent, sieur de Gournay (1712-1759). The principles of the school had been put forward in 1755
by Richard Cantillon, a French merchant of Irish extraction (Essai sur la nature du Commerce en
général), whose biography Jevons has elucidated,(2) and whom he regards as the true founder of
political economy; but it was in the hands of Quesnay and Gournay(3) that they acquired a
systematic form, and became the creed of a united group of thinkers and practical men, bent on
carrying them into action. The members of the group called themselves "les économistes," but it is
more convenient, because unambiguous, to designate them by the name "physiocrates," invented
by Dupont de Nemours, who was one of thei number. In this name, intended to express the
fundainental idea of the school, much more is implied than the subjection of the phenomena of the
social, and in particular the economic, world to fixed relations of co-existence and succession. This
is the positive doctrine which lies at the bottom of all true science. But the law of nature referred to in
the title of the sect was something quite different. The theological dogma which represented all the
movements of the universe as diected by divine wisdom and benevolence to the production of the
greatest possible sum of happiness had been transformed in the hands of the metaphysicians into
the conception of a jus naturae, a harmonious and beneficial code established by the favourite entity
of these thinkers, Nature, antecedent to human institutions, and furnishing the model to which they
should be made to conform. This idea, which Buckle apparently supposes to have been an
invention of Hutcheson's, had come down through Roman juridical theory from the speculations of
Greece.(4) It was taken in hand by the modern negative school from Hobbes to Rousseau, and
used as a powerful weapon of assault upon the existing order of society, with which the "natural"
order was perpetually contrasted as offering the imperfect type from which fact had deplorably
diverged. The theory received different applications according to the diversity of minds or
cicumstances. By some it was diected against the artificial manner of the times, by others against
contemporary political institutions; it was specialty employed by the physiocrats in criticising the
economic practice of European Governments.
The general political doctrine is as follows. Society is composed of a number of individuals all
having the same natural rights. if all do not possess (as some members of the negative school
maintained) equal capacities, each can at least best understand his own interest, and is led by
nature to follow it. The social union is really a contract between these individuals, the object of which
is the limitation of the natural freedom of each, just so far as it is inconsistent with the rights of the
others. Government, though necessary, is a necessary evil; and the governing power appointed by
consent should be limited to the amount of interference absolutely required to secure the fulfilment
of the contract. In the economic sphere, this implies the right of the individual to such natural
enjoyments as he can acquire by his labour. That labour, therefore, should be undisturbed and
unfettered; and its fruits should be guaranteed to the possessor; in other words, property should be
sacred. Each citizen must be allowed to make the most of his labour; and therefore freedom of
exchange should be ensured, and competition in the market should be unrestricted, no monopolies
or privileges being permitted to exist.
The physiocrats then proceed with the economic analysis as follows. Only those labours are truly
"productive" which add to the quantity of raw materials available for the purposes of man; and the
real annual addition to the wealth of the community consists of the excess of the mass of
agricultural products (including, of course, minerals) over their cost of production. On the amount of
this "product net" depends the well-being of the community, and the possibility of its advance in
civilization. The manufacturer merely gives a new form to the materials extracted from the earth; the
higher value of the object, after it has passed through his hands, only represents the quantity of
provisions and other materials used and consumed in its elaboration. Commerce does nothing more
than transfer the wealth akeady existing from one hand to another; what the trading classes gain
thereby is acquired at the cost of the nation, and it is desirable that its amount should be as small as
possible. The occupation of the manufacturer and merchant, as well as the liberal professions, and
every kind of personal service, are "useful" indeed, but they are "sterile," drawing their income, not
from any fund which they themselves create, but from the superauous earnings of the agricultlvists.
Perfect freedom of trade not only rests, as we have already seen, on the foundation of natural right,
but is also recommended by the consideration that it makes the "produit net," on which all wealth
and general progress depend, as large as possible. "Laissez faire, laissez passer" should therefore
be the motto of Governments. The revenue of the State, which must be derived altogether from this
net product, ought to be raised in the most direct and simplest way, namely, by a single impost of
the nature of a land tax.(5)
The special doctrine relating to the exclusive productiveness of agriculture arose out of a confusion
between "value" on the one hand and "matter and energy" on the other. Smith and others have
shown that the attempt to fix the character of "sterility" on manufactures and commerce was
founded in error. And the proposal of a single impôt territorial falls to the ground with the doctrine on
which it was based. But such influence as the school exerted depended little, if at all, on these
peculiar tenets, which indeed some of its members did not hold, The effective result of its teaching
was mainly destructive. It continued in a more systematic form the efforts in favour of the freedom of
industry already begun in England and France. The essential historical once of the physiocrats was
to discredit radically the methods followed by the European Governments in their dealings with
industry. For such criticism as theirs there was, indeed, ample room: the policy of Colbert, which
could be only temporarily useful, had been abusively extended and intensified; Governmental action
had intruded itself into the minutest details of business, and every process of manufacture and
transaction of trade was hampered by legislative restrictions. It was to be expected that the
reformers should, in the spirit of the negative philosophy, exaggerate the vices of established
systems; and there can be no doubt that they condemned too absolutely the economic action of the
State, both in principle and in its historic manifestations, and pushed the "laissez faire" doctrine
beyond its just limits. But this was a necessary incident of their connection with the revolutionary
movement, of which they really formed one wing. In the course of that movement, the primitive
social contract, the sovereignty of the people, and other dogmas now seen to be untenable, were
habitually invoked in the region of politics proper, and had a transitory utility as ready and effective
instruments of warfare. And so also in the economic sphere the doctrines of natural rights of buying
and selling, of the sufficiency of enlightened selfishness as a guide in mutual dealings, of the
certainty that each member of the society will understand and follow his true interests, and of the
coincidence of those interests with the public welfare, though they will not bear a dispassionate
examination, were temporarily useful as convenient and serviceable weapons for the overthrow of
the established order. The tendency of the school was undoubtedly to consecrate the spirit of
individualism, and the state of non-government. But this tendency, which may with justice be
severely condemned in economists of the present time, was then excusable because inevitable.
And, whilst it now impedes the work of reconstruction which is for us the order of the day, it then
aided the process of social demolition, which was the necessary, though deplorable, condition of a
new organisation.
These conclusions as to the revolutionary tendencies of the school are not at all affected by the fact
that the form of government preferred by Quesnay and some of his chief followers was what they
called a legal despotism, which should embrace within itself both the legislative and the executive
function. The reason for this preference was that an enlightened central power could more promptly
and efficaciously introduce the policy they advocated than an assembly representing divergent
opinions, and fettered by constitutional checks and limitations. Turgot, as we know, used the
absolute power of the crown to carry into effect some of his measures for the liberation of industry,
though he ultimately failed because unsustained by the requisite force of character in Louis XVI. But
what the physiocratic idea with respect to the normal method of government was appears from
Quesnay's advice to the dauphin, that when he became king he should "do nothing, but let the laws
rule," the laws having been of course first brought into conformity with the jus naturae. The partiality
of the school for agriculture was in harmony with the sentiment in favour of "nature" and primitive
simplicity which then showed itself in so many forms in France, especially in combination with the
revolutionary spirit, and of which Rousseau was the most eloquent exponent. It was also associated
in these writers with a just indignation at the wretched state in which the rural labourers of France
had been left by the scandalous neglect of the superior orders of society -- a state of which the
terrible picture drawn by La Bruyère is an indestructible record. The members of the physiocratic
group were undoubtedly men of thorough uprightness, and inspired with a sincere desire for the
public good, especially for the material and moral elevation of the working classes. Quesnay was
physician to Louis XV, and resided in the palace at Versailles; but in the midst of that corrupt court
he maintained his integrity, and spoke with manly frankness what he believed to be the truth. And
never did any statesman devote himself with greater singleness of purpose or more earnest
endeavour to the service of his country than Turgot, who was the principal practical representative of
the school.
The publications in which Quesnay expounded his system were the following:(6) --Two articles, on
"Fermiers" and on "Grains," in the Encyclopédie of Diderot and D'Alembert (1756, 1757); a
discourse on the law of nature in the Physiocratic of Dupont de Nemours (1768); Maximes
génératles de gouvernement économique d'un royaume agricole (1758), and the simultaneously
published Taleau Économique avec son explication, ou Extrait des conomies Royales de Sully (with
the celebrated motto "pauvres paysans, pauvre royaume; pauvre royaume, pauvre roi"); Dialogue
sur le commerce et les travaux des artisans; and other minor pieces. The Tableau Economique,
though on account of its dryness and abstract form it met with little general favour, may be
considered the principal manifesto of the school. It was regarded by the followers of Quesnay as
entitled to a place amongst the foremost products of human wisdom, and is named by the elder
Mirabeau, in a passage quoted by Adam Smith,(7) as one of the three great inventions which have
contributed most to the stability of political societies, the other two being those of writing and of
money. Its object was to exhibit by means of certain formulas the way in which the products of
agriculture, which is the only source of wealth, would in a state of perfect liberty be distributed
among the several classes of the community (namely, the productive classes of the proprietors and
cultivators of land, and the unproductive class composed of manufacturers and merchants), and to
represent by other formulas the modes of distribution which take place under systems of
Governmental restraint and regulation, with the evil results arising to the whole society from different
degrees of such violations of the natural order. It follows from Quesnay's theoretic views that the
one thing deserving the solicitude of the practical economist and the statesman is the increase of
the net product; and he infers also what Smith afterwards affirmed on not quite the same ground,
that the interest of the landowner is "strictly and inseparably connected with the general interest of
the society."(8)
M. de Gournay, as we have seen, was regarded as one of the founders of the school, and appears
to have exercised some influence even upon the formation of Quesnay's own opinions. With the
exception of translations of Culpeper and Child,(9) Gournay wrote nothing but memois addressed to
ministers, which have not seen the light; but we have a full statement of his views in the loge
dedicated to his memory by his illustrious friend Turgot. Whilst Quesnay had spent his youth amidst
rural scenes, and had been early familiar with the labours of the field, Gournay had been bred as a
merchant, and had passed from the counting-house to the once of intendant of commerce. They
thus approached the study of political economy from different sides, and this diversity of their
antecedents may in part explain the amount of divergence which existed between their views.
Gournay softened the rigour of Quesnay's system, and brought it nearer to the truth, by rejecting
what Smith calls its "capital error" -- the doctrine, namely, of the unproductiveness of manufactures
and commerce. He directed his efforts to the assertion and vindication of the principle of industrial
liberty, and it was by him that this principle was formulated in the phrase, since so often heard for
good and for evil, "Laissez faire et laissez passer." One of the earliest and most complete adherents
of the physiocratic school, as well as an ardent and unwearied propagator of its doctrines, was
Victor Mirabeau, whose sincere and independent, though somewhat perverse and whimsical,
character is familiar to English readers through Carlyle's essay on his more celebrated son. He had
expressed some physiocratic views earlier than Quesnay, but owned the latter for his spiritual
father, and adopted most of his opinions, the principal difference being that he was favourable to the
petite as opposed to the grande culture, which latter was preferred by his chief as giving, not indeed
the largest gross, but the largest net product. Miabeau's principal writings were Ami des Hommes,
ou traité sur la population (1756, 1760), Théorie de l'impôt (176), Les Éconimiques (1769) and
Philosophie rurale, ou Économie générale et politique de l'Agriculture (1763). The last of these was
the earliest complete exposition of the physiocratic system. Another earnest and persevering
apostle of the system was Dupont de Nemours (1739-1817), known by his treatises De l'exportation
et l'imortation des grains (1764, De l'origine et des progrès d'une science nouvelle (1767), Du
commerce de la Compagnie des Indies (1767), and especially by his more comprehensive work
Physiocratie, ou Consitution naturelle du gouvernement le plus avantageus ou genre humain
(1768). The title of this work gave, as has been already mentioned, a name to the school. Another
formal exposition of the system, to which Adam Smith refers as the "most distinct and best
connected account" of it, was produced by Mercier-Lariviére, under the title L'Ordre naturel et
essentiel des sociétés politiques (1767), a title which is interesting as embodying the idea of the jus
naturae.(10) Both he and Dupont de Nemours professed to study human communities, not only in
relation to their economic, but also to their political and general social aspects; but, notwithstanding
these larger pretensions, their views were commonly restricted in the main to the economic sphere;
at least material considerations decidedly preponderated in their inquiries, as was naively indicated
by Larivière when he said, "Property, security, liberty -- these comprise the whole social order; the
right of property is a tree of which all the institutions of society are branches."
The most eminent member of the group was without doubt Anne Robert Jacques Turgot (1727-
1781). This is not the place to speak of his noble practical activity, first as intendant of Limoges, and
afterwards for a brief period as finance minister, or of the circumstances which led to his removal
from office, and the consequent failure of his efforts for the salvation of France. His economic views
are explained in the introductions to his edicts and ordinances, in letters and occasional papers, but
especially in his Réflexions sur la formation et la distribution des richesses (1766). This is a
condensed but eminently clear and attractive exposition of the fundamental principles of political
economy, as they were conceived by the physiocrats. It embodies, indeed, the erroneous no less
than the sound doctrines of that school; but several subjects, especially the various forms of land-
economy, the different employments of capital, and the legitimacy of interest, are handled in a
generally just as well as striking manner; and the mode of presentation of the ideas, and the
luminous arrangement of the whole, are Turgot's own. The treatise, which contains a surprising
amount of matter in proportion to its length, must always retain a place among the classics of the
science.
The physiocratic school never obtained much direct popular influence, even in its native country,
though it strongly attracted many of the more gifted and earnest minds. Its members, writing on dry
subjects in an austere and often heavy style, did not find acceptance with a public which demanded
before all things charm of manner in those who addressed it. When Morellet, one of their number,
entered the lists with Galiani, it was seen how espirit; and eloquence could triumph over science,
solid indeed, but clumsy in its movements.(11) The physiocratic tenets, which were in fact partially
erroneous, were regarded by many as chemerical, and were ridiculed in the contemporary literature,
as, for example, the impôt unique by Voltaire in his L'homme aux quarante écus, which was directed
in particular against Mercier-Larivière. It was justly objected to the group that they were too absolute
in their view of things; they supposed, as Smith remarks in speaking of Quesnay, that the body-
politic could thrive only under one precise régime, -- that, namely, which they recommended, -- and
thought their doctrines universally and immediately applicable in practice.(12) They did not, as
theorists, sufficiently take into account national diversities,(13) or different stages in social
development; nor did they as politicians, adequately estimate the impediments which ignorance,
prejudice, and interested opposition present to enlightened statesmanship. It is possible that Turgot
himself, as Grimm suggests, owed his failure in part to the too unbending rigour of his policy and the
absence of any attempt at conciliation. Be this as it may, his defeat helped to impair the credit of his
principles, which were represented as having been tried and found wanting.
The physiocratic system, after guiding in some degree the policy of the Constituent Assembly, and
awakening a few echoes here and there in foreign countries, soon ceased to exist as a living power;
but the good elements it comprised were not lost to mankind, being incorporated into the sounder
and more complete construction of Adam Smith.
ITALY
In Italy, as in the other European nations, there was little activity in the economic field during the first
half of the eighteenth century. It was then, however, that a really remarkable man appeared, the
archdeacon Salustio Antonio Bandini (1677-1760), author of the Discorso sulla Maremma Sienese,
written in 1737, but not published till 1775. The object of the work was to raise the Maremma from
the wretched condition into which it had fallen through the decay of agriculture. This decay he
showed to be, at least in part, the result of the wretched fiscal system which was in force; and his
book led to important reforms in Tuscany, where his name is held in high honour. Not only by
Pecchio and other Italian writers, but by Roscher also, he is alleged to have anticipated some
leading doctrines of the physiocrats, but this claim is disputed. There was a remarkable renascence
of economic studies in Italy during the latter half of the century, partly due to French influence, and
partly, it would appear, to improved government in the northern states.
The movement at first followed the lines of the mercantile school. Thus, in Antonio Broggia's Trattati
dei tributi e delle monete e del governo politico della societá (1743), and Girolamo Belloni's
Dissertazione sopra il commercio (1750), which seems to have had a success and reputation much
above its merits, mercantilist tendencies decidedly preponderate. But the most distinguished writer
who represented that economic doctrine in Italy in the last century was Antonio Genovesi, a
Neapolitan (1712-1769). He felt deeply the depressed intellectual and moral state of his fellow-
countrymen, and aspired after a revival of philosophy and reform of education as the first condition
of progress and well-being. With the object of protecting him from the theological persecutions
which threatened him on account of his advanced opinions, Bartolomeo Intieri, of whom we shall
hear again in relation to Galiani, founded in 1755, expressly for Genovesi, a chair of commerce and
mechanics, one of the conditions of foundation being that it should never be filled by a monk. This
was the first professorship of economics established in Europe; the second was founded at
Stockholm in 1758, and the third in Lombardy ten years later, for Beccaria. The fruit of the labours of
Genovesi in this chair was his Lezioni di commercio, ossia di economia civile (1769), which
contained the first systematic treatment of the whole subject which had appeared in Italy. As the
model for Italian imitation he held up England, a country for which, says Pecchio, he had a
predilection almost amounting to fanaticism. He does not rise above the false economic system
which England then pursued; but he rejects some of the grosser errors of the school to which he
belonged; he advocates the freedom of the corn trade, and deprecates regulation of the interest on
loans. In the spirit of his age, he denounces the relics of medieval institutions, such as entails and
tenures in mortmain, as impediments to the national prosperity. Ferdinando Galiani was another
distinguished disciple of the mercantile school. Before he had completed his twenty-first year he
published a work on money (Detta moneta libri cinque, 1750), the principles of which are supposed
to have been dictated by two experienced practical men, the Marquis Rinuccini and Bartolomeo
Intieri, whose name we have already met. But his reputation was made by a book written in French
and published in Paris, where he was secretary of embassy, in 1770, namely, his Dialogues sur le
commerce des blés. This work, by its light and pleasing style, and the vivacious wit with which it
abounded, delighted Voltaire, who spoke of it as a book in the production of which Plato and Molière
might have been combined!(14) The author, says Pecchio, treated his arid subject as Fontenelle did
the vortices of Descartes, or Algarotti the Newtonian system of the world. The question at issue was
that of the freedom of the corn trade, then much agitated, and, in particular, the policy of the royal
edict of 1764, which permitted the exportation of grain so long as the price had not arrived at a
certain height. The general principle he maintains is that the best system in regard to this trade is to
have no system -- countries differently circumstanced requiring, according to him, different modes of
treatment. This seems a lame and impotent conclusion from the side of science; yet doubtless the
physiocrats, with whom his controversy lay, prescribed on this, as on other subjects, rules too rigid
for the safe guidance of statesmen, and Galiani may have rendered a real service by protesting
against their absolute solutions of practical problems. He fell, however, into some of the most
serious errors of the mercantilists -- holding, as indeed did also Voltare and even Verri, that one
country cannot gain without another losing, and in his earlier treatise going so far as to defend the
action of Governments in debasing the currency.
Amongst the Italian economists who were most under the influence of the modern spirit, and in
closest harmony with the general movement which was impelling the Western nations towards a
new social order, Cesare Beccaria (1738-1794) holds a foremost place. He is best known by his
celebrated treatise Dei delitti e delle pene, by which Voltaire said he had made himself a benefactor
of all Europe, and which, we are told, has been translated into twenty-two languages. The Empress
Catherine having invited him to fix his residence at St. Petersburg the Austrian Government of
Lombardy, in order to keep him at home, established expressly for him a chair of political economy;
and in his Elementi di economia pubblica (1769-1771; not published, however, till 1804) are
embodied his teachings as professor. The work is unfinished: he had divided the whole subject
under the heads of agriculture, manufactures, commerce, taxation, government; but he has treated
adequately only the first two heads, and the last two not at all, having been called to take part in the
councils of the state. He was in some degree under the influence of physiocratic ideas, and holds
that agriculture is the only strictly productive form of industry, whilst manufacturers and artisans are
a sterile class. He was strongly opposed to monopolies and privileges, and to corporations in arts
and trades; in general he warmly advocated internal industrial freedom, though in regard to foreign
commerce a protectionist. In the special case of the corn trade he was not, any more than Galiani, a
partisan of absolute liberty. His exposition of economic principles is concise and sententious, and he
often states correctly the most important considerations relating to his subject without adding the
developments which would be desirable to assist comprehension and strengthen conviction. Thus
on fixed capital (capitali fondatori), as distinct from circulating (annui), in its application to
agriculture, he presents in a condensed form essentially the same explanations as Turgot about the
same time gave; and on the division of labour and the circumstances which cause different rates of
wages in different employments, he in substance comes near to Smith, but without the fulness of
illustration which is so attractive a feature of the Wealth of Nations. Pietro Verri (1728-1797), an
intimate and lifelong friend of Beccaria, was for twenty-five years one of the principal directors of the
administration of Lombardy, in which capacity he originated many economic and other reforms. In
his Riflessioni sulle leggi vincolanti, principalmente nel commercio de' grani (written in 1769, printed
in 1796), he considers the question of the regulation of the corn trade both historically and in the
light of theoretic principles, and arrives at the conclusion that liberty is the best remedy against
famine and against excessive fluctuations of price. He is generally opposed to Governmental
interference with internal commerce, as well as to trade corporations, and the attempts to limit prices
or fix the rate of interest, but is in favour of the protection of national industry by a judiciously framed
tariff. These views are explained in his Meditazioni sull' economia politica (1771), an elementary
treatise on the science, which was received with favour, and translated into several foreign
languages. A primary principle with him is what he calls the augmentation of reproduction -- that is,
in Smith's language, of "the annual produce of the land and labour" of a nation; and by its tendency
to promote or to restrict this augmentation, he tests every enactment and institution. Accordingly,
unlike Beccaria, he prefers the petite the grande culture, as giving a larger total produce. In dealing
with taxation, he rejects the physiocratic proposal of a single impôt territorial.(15) Giovanni R. Carli
(1720-1796), also an official promoter of the reforms in the government of Austrian Lombardy,
besides learned and sound treatises on money, was author of Ragionamenti sopra i bilanci
economici delle nazioni, in which he shows the falsity of the notion that a state gains or loses in
foreign commerce according to the so-called balance of trade. In his letter to Pompeo Neri Sul libero
commercio de' grani (1771), he takes up a position similar to that of Galiani, regarding the question
of the freedom of the corn trade as not so much a scientific as an administrative one, to be dealt
with differently under different local or other conditions. Rejecting the physiocratic doctrine of the
exclusive productiveness of agriculture, he illustrates in an interesting way the necessity of various
economic classes in a society, and the reflex agency of manufactures in stimulating the cultivation
of the soil. Giambattista Vasco (1733-1796) wrote discourses on several questions proposed by
academies and sovereigns. In these he condemns trade corporations and the attempts by
Governments to fix the price of bread and to limit the interest on loans. In advocating the system of
a peasant proprietary, he suggests that the law should determine the minimum and maximum
portions ot land which a citizen should be permitted to possess. He also, with a view to prevent the
undue accumulation of property, proposes the abolition of the right of bequest, and the equal
division of the inheritance amongst the children of the deceased, Gaetano Filangieri (1762-1788),
one of the Italian writers of the last century whose names are most widely known throughout
Europe, devoted to economic questions the second book of his Scienza della legislazion (5 vols.,
1780-1786). Filled with reforming ardour and a passionate patriotism, he employed his vehement
eloquence in denouncing all the abuses of his time. Apparently without any knowledge of Adam
Smith, he insists on unlimited freedom of trade, calls for the abolition of the medieval institutions
which impeded production and national well-being, and condemns the colonial system then followed
by England, Spain, and Holland. He prophesies, as Raynal, Turgot, and Genovesi had done before
him, that all America would one day be independent, a prediction which probably helped to elicit
Benjamin Franklin's tribute of admiration for his work. Rather a propagator than a discoverer, he
sometimes adopted from others erroneous opinions, as, for example, when he approves the impôt
unique of the physiocrats. On the whole, however, he represents the most advanced political and
social tendencies of his age; whilst strongly contrasted with Beccaria in temperament and style, he
was a worthy labourer in the same cause of national and universal progress. Ludovico Ricci (1742-
1799) was author of an able report Sulla riforma degli istituti pii della città di Modena (1787). He
treated the subject of poor relief and charitable institutions in so general a way that the work
possesses a universal and permanent interest. He dwells on the evils of indiscriminate relief as
tending to increase the misery it seeks to remove, and as lowering the moral character of a
population. He exposes especially the abuses connected with lying-in and foundling hospitals.
There is much in him which is akin to the views of Malthus; like him he is opposed to any state
provision for the destitute. who ought, he thinks, to be left to voluntary private beneficence.
Ferdinando Paoletti (1717-1801) was an excellent and public-spirited priest, who did much for the
diffusion of intelligence amongst the agricultural population of Tuscany, and for the lightening of the
taxes which pressed upon them he corresponded with Mirabeau ("Friend of Men"), and appears to
have accepted the physiocratic doctrines, at least in their general substance. he was author of
Pensieri sopra l'agricoltura (1769), and of I verri mezzi di render felici le società (1772); in the latter
he advocates the freedom of the corn trade. The tract Il Colbertismo (1791) by Count Francesco
Mengotti is a vigorous protest against the extreme policy of prohibition and protection, which may
still be read with interest. Mengotti also wrote (1791) a treatise Del commercio de' Romani, directed
mainly against the exaggerations of Huet in his Histoire du commerce et de la navigation des
anciens (1716), and useful as marking the broad difference between the ancient and modern
civilizations.
Here lastly may be mentioned another Italian thinker who, eminently original and even eccentric,
cannot easily be classed among his contemporaries, though some Continental writers of our own
century have exhibited similar modes of thought. This was Giammaria Ortes (1713-1790). He is
opposed to the liberalist tendencies of his time, but does not espouse the doctrines of the mercantile
system, rejecting the theory of the balance of trade, and demanding commercial freedom. It is in the
Middle Ages that he finds his social and economic type. He advocates the maintenance of church
property, is averse to the ascendency of the money power, and has the medieval dislike for interest
on loans. He entertains the singular idea that the wealth of communities is always and everywhere
in a fixed ratio to their population, the latter being determined by the former. Poverty, therefore,
necessarily waits on wealth, and the rich, in becoming so, only gain what the poor lose. Those who
are interested in the improvement of the condition of the people labour in vain, so long as they direct
their efforts to the increase of the sum of the national wealth, which it is beyond their power to alter,
instead of to the distribution of that wealth, which it is possible to modify. The true remedy for
poverty lies in mitigating the gain-pursuing propensities in the rich and in men of business. Ortes
studied in a separate work the subject of population; he formulates its increase as "geometrical," but
recognizes that, as a limit is set to such increase amongst the lower animals by mutual destruction,
so is it in the human species by "reason" -- the "prudential restraint" of which Malthus afterwards
made so much. He regards the institution of celibacy as no less necessary and advantageous than
that of marriage. He enunciates what has since been known as the "law of diminishing returns to
agricultural industry." He was careless as to the diffusion of his writings; and hence they remained
almost unknown till they were included in the Custodi collection of Italian economists, when they
attracted much attention by the combined sagacity and waywardness which marked their author's
intellectual character.
SPAIN
The same breath of a new era which was in the air elsewhere in Europe made itself felt also in
Spain.
In the earlier part of the eighteenth century Geronimo Ustariz had written his Teorica y Practica del
Comercio y Marina (1724; published, 1740; Eng. transl. by John Kippax, 1751; French by
Forbonnais, 1753), in which he carries mercantile principles to their utmost extreme.
The reforming spirit of the latter half of the century was best represented in that country by Pedro
Rodriguez, Count of Campomanes (1723-1802). He pursued with ardour the same studies and in
some degree the same policy as his illustrious contemporary Turgot, without, however, having
arrived at so advanced a point of view. He was author of Respuesta fiscal sobre abolir la tasa y
establecer et comercio de granos (1764), Discurso sobre el fomento de industria popolar (1774),
and Discurso sobre la educacion de las artesanos y su fomento (1775). By means of these writings,
justly eulogised by Robertson,(16) as well as by his personal efforts as minister, he sought to
establish the freedom of the corn trade, to remove the hindrances to industry arising from medieval
survivals, to have a large development to manufactures, and to liberate agriculture from the odious
burdens to which it was subject. He saw that, notwithstanding the enlightened administration of
Charles III, Spain still suffered from the evil results of the blind confidence reposed by her people in
her gold mines, and enforced the lesson that the real sources of the wealth and power of his country
must be sought, not in America, but in her own industry.
In both Italy and Spain, as is well observed by Comte,(17) the impulse towards social change took
principally the direction of economic reform, because the pressure exercised by Governments
prevented so large a measure of free speculation in the fields of philosophy and general politics as
was possible in France. In Italy, it may be added, the traditions of the great industrial past of the
northern cities of that country also tended to fix attention chiefly on the economic side of public
policy and legislation.
GERMANY
We have seen that in Italy and England political economy had its beginnings in the study of practical
questions relating chiefly to money or to foreign commerce. In Germany it arose (as Roscher has
shown) out of the so-called cameralistic sciences. Soon after the close of the Middle Ages there
existed in most German countries a council, known as the Kammer (Lat. camera), which was
occupied with the management of the public domain and the guardianship of regal rights. The
Emperor Maximilian found this institution existing in Burgundy, and established, in imitation of it,
aulic councils at Innspruck and Vienna in 1498 and 1501. Not only finance and taxation, but
questions also of economic police, came to be entrusted to these bodies. A special preparation
became necessary for their members, and chairs of cameralistic science were founded in
universities for the teaching of the appropriate body of doctrine. One side of the instruction thus
given borrowed its materials from the sciences of external nature, dealing, as it did, with forestry,
mining, general technology, and the like; the other related to the conditions of national prosperity as
depending on human relations and institutions; and out of the latter, German political economy was
at first developed.
In no country had mercantilist views a stronger hold than in Germany, though in none, in the period
we are now considering, did the system of the balance of trade receive a less extensive practical
application. All the leading German economists of the seventeenth century -- Bornitz, Besold, Klock,
Becher, Horneck, Seckendorf, and Schröder -- stand on the common basis of the mercantile
doctrine. And the same may be said of the writers of the first half of the eighteenth century in
general, and notably of Justi (d. 1771), who was the author of the first systematic German treatise
on political economy, a work which, from its currency as a text-book, had much effect on the
formation of opinion. Only in Zincke (1692-1769) do we find occasional expressions of a circle of
ideas at variance with the dominant system, and pointing in the direction of industrial freedom. But
these writers, except from the national point of view, are unimportant, not having exercised any
influence on the general movement of European thought.
The principles of the physiocratic system met with a certain amount of favour in Germany. Karl
Friedrich, Margrave of Baden, wrote for the use of his sons an Abrégé des principes d'Économie
Politique, 1772, which is in harmony with the doctrines of that system. It possesses, however, little
scientific value. Schlettwein (1731-1802) and Mauvillon (1743-1794) were followers of the same
school. Theodor Schmalz (1764-183a), who is commonly named as "the last of the physiocrats,"
may be here mentioned, though somewhat out of the historic order. He compares Colbertism with
the Ptolemaic system, physiocratism with the Copernican. Adam Smith he represents as the Tycho
Brahe of political economy -- a man of eminent powers, who could not resist the force of truth in the
physiocrats, but partly could not divest himself of rooted prejudices, and partly was ambitious of the
fame of a discoverer and a reconciler of divergent systems. Though Smith was now "the fashion,"
Schmalz could not doubt that Quesnay's doctrine was alone true, and would ere long be triumphant
everywhere.(18)
Just before the appearance of Smith, as in England Steuart and in Italy Genovesi, so in Austria
Sonnenfels (1733-1817), the first distinguished economist of that country, sought to present the
mercantile system in a modified and more enlightened form; and his work (Grundsätze der Polizei,
Handlung, und Finanz, 1765; 8th ed., 1822) exercised even during a considerable part of the
present century much influence on opinion and on policy in Austria.
But the greatest German economist of the eighteenth century was, in Roscher's opinion, Justus
Möser (1720-1794), the author of Patriotische Phantasieen (1774), a series of fragments, which,
Goethe nevertheless declares, form "ein wahrhaites Ganzes." The poet was much influenced by
Möser in his youth, and has eulogised in the Dichtung und Wahrheit (Bk. xiii) his spirit, intellect, and
character, and his thorough insight into all that goes on in the social world. Whilst others occupied
themselves with larger and more prominent public affairs and transactions, Möser observed and
reproduced the common daily life of his nation, and the thousand "little things" which compose the
texture of popular existence. He has been compared to Franklin for the homeliness, verve, and
freshness of his writings. In opinions he is akin to the Italian Ortes. He is opposed to the whole spirit
of the "Aufkärung", and to the liberal and rationalistic direction of which Smith's work became
afterwards the expression. He is not merely conservative but reactionary, manifesting a preference
for medieval institutions such as the trade guilds, and, like Carlyle in our own time, seeing
advantages even in serfdom, when compared with the sort of freedom enjoyed by the modern
drudge. He has a marked antipathy for the growth of the money power and of manufactures on the
large scale, and for the highly developed division of labour. He is opposed to absolute private
property in land, and would gladly see revived such a system of restrictions as in the interest of the
state, the commune, and the family were imposed on medieval ownership. In his wayward and
caustic style, he often criticises effectively the doctrinaire narrowness of his contemporaries, throws
out many striking ideas, and in particular sheds real light on the economic phenomena and general
social conditions of the Middle Ages.
THE NETHERLANDS
In the Netherlands, tendencies towards the new economic ideas showed themselves about the
middle of the seventeenth century. Dirck Graswinckel (1600-1668) advocated free trade in corn, and
was in general opposed to restrictions on industry. Pieter de la Court (1618-1685) dealt in a similar
spirit with most of the practical questions of his country and age. He is in favour of the perfect liberty
of citizens to buy and sell, produce and consume, as well as to learn and teach; and he sharply
criticised the system of trade corporations. He was in literary alliance with the Grand Pensionary,
John de Witt. His principal work (Aanwysing def heilsame politike gronden en Maximan van de
Republike van Hollanden Westfriesland, 1669)(19) was commonly attributed to that statesman, it is
better known in the French translation (1709) which appeared under the title of Memoirs de Jean de
Witt. Jan de la Court (1622-1660), the brother of Pieter, followed the same direction, The works of
Salmasius (1633, 1640) were of great importance in the controversy on the necessity and
lawfulness of interest on money loans.
ADAM SMITH, WITH HIS IMMEDIATE PREDECESSORS
AND HIS FOLLOWERS.
England.
The stagnation in economic inquiry which showed itself in England in the early part of the eighteenth
century was not broken by any notable manifestation before 1735, when Bishop Berkeley put
forward in his Querist, with much force and point, views opposed to those of the mercantile school
on the nature of national wealth and the functions of money, though not without an admixture of
grave error. But soon a more decisive advance was made. Whilst in France the physiocrats were
working after their own fashion towards the construction of a definitive system of political economy,
a Scottish thinker of the first order was elucidating, in a series of short but pregnant essays, some of
the fundamental conceptions of the science. What had been written on these questions in the
English language before his time had remained almost altogether within the limits of the directly
practical sphere. With Locke, indeed, the general system of the modern critical philosophy had
come into relation with economic inquiry, but only in a partial and indeterminate way. But in Hume
the most advanced form of this philosophy was represented, and his appearance in the field of
economics decisively, marks the tendency of the latter order of speculation to place itself in
connection with the largest and deepest thought on human nature and general human history. Most
of the essays here referred to first appeared in 1752, in a volume entitled Political Discourses, and
the number was completed in the collection of Essays and Treatises on Several Subjects, published
in the following year. The most important of them are those on Commerce, on Money, on Interest,
and on the Balance of Trade. Yet these should not be separated from the rest, for, notwithstanding
the unconnected form of these little treatises, there runs through them a profound unity of thought,
so that they indeed compose in a certain sense an economic system. They exhibit in full measure
Hume's wonderful acuteness and subtlety, which indeed sometimes dispose him to paradox, in
combination with the breadth, the absence of prejudice, and the social sympathies which so
eminently distinguish him; and they offer, besides, the charm of his easy and natural style and his
rare power of lucid exposition.
In the essay on money he refutes the mercantilist error, which tended to confound it with wealth.
"Men and commodities," he says, "are the real strength of any community." "In the national stock of
labour consists all real power and riches." Money is only the oil which makes the movements of the
mechanism of commerce more smooth and easy. He shows that, from the domestic as
distinguished from the international point of view, the absolute quantity of money, supposed as of
fixed amount, in a country is of no consequence, whilst an excessive quantity, larger, that is, than is
required for the interchange of commodities, may be injurious as raising prices and driving
foreigners from the home markets. He goes so far, in one or two places, as to assert that the value
of money is chiefly fictitious or conventional, a position which cannot be defended; but it must not be
pressed against him, as he builds nothing on it. He has some very ingenious observations (since,
however, questioned by J. S. Mill) on the effects of the increase of money in a country in stimulating
industry during the interval which takes place before the additional amount is sufficiently diffused to
alter the whole scale of prices. He shows that the fear of the money of an industrious community
being lost to it by passing into foreign countries is groundless, and that, under a system of freedom,
the distribution of the precious metals which is adapted to the requirements of trade will
spontaneously establish itself. "In short, a Government has great reason to preserve with care its
people and its manufactures; its money it may safely trust to the course of human affairs without
fear or jealousy."
A very important service was rendered by his treatment of the rate of interest. He exposes the
erroneous idea often entertained that it depends on the quantity of money in a country, and shows
that the reduction of it must in general be the result of "the increase of industry and frugality, of arts
and commerce," so that it may serve as a barometer, its lowness being an almost infallible sign of
the flourishing condition of a people. It may be observed in passing that in the essay devoted to this
subject he brings out a principle of human nature which economists too often overlook, "the
constant and insatiable desire of the mind for exercise and employment," and the consequent action
of ennui in prompting to exertion.
With respect to commerce, he points to its natural foundation in what has since been called "the
territorial division of labour," and proves that the prosperity of one nation, instead of being a
hindrance, is a help to that of its neighbours. "Not only as a man, but as a British subject," he says,
"I pray for the flourishing commerce of Germany, Spain, Italy, and even France itself." He condemns
the "numberless bars, obstructions, and imposts which all nations of Europe, and none more than
England, have put upon trade." Yet on the question of protection to national industry he is not quite
at the free-trade point of view, for he approves of a tax on German linen as encouraging home
manufactures, and of a tax on brandy as increasing the sale of rum and supporting our southern
colonies. Indeed it has been justly observed that there are in him several traces of a refined
mercantilism, and that he represents a state of opinion in which the transition irom the old to the new
views is not yet completely effected.
We cannot do more than refer to the essay on taxes, in which, amongst other things, he repudiates
the impt unique of the physiocrats, and to that on public credit, in which he criticises the "new
paradox that public encumbrances are of themselves advantageous, independent of the necessity
of contracting them," and objects, perhaps too absolutely, to the modern expedient of raising the
money required for national enterprises by way of loan, and so shifting our burdens upon the
shoulders of posterity.
The characteristics of Hume, which are most important in the history of economic investigation, are
(1) his practice of bringing economic facts into connection with all the weighty interests of social and
political life, and (2) his tendency to introduce the historical spirit into the study of those facts. He
admirably illustrates the mutual action of the several branches of industry, and the influences of
progress in the arts of production and in commerce on general civilisation, exhibits the striking
contrasts of the ancient and modern system of life (see especially the essay On the Populousness
of Ancient Nations), and considers almost every phenomenon which comes under discussion in its
relations to the contemporary stage of social development. It cannot be doubted that Hume
exercised a most important influence on Adam Smith, who in the Wealth of Nations(20) calls him
"by far the most illustrious philosopher and historian of the present age," and who esteemed his
character so highly that, after a friendship of many years had been terminated by Hume's decease,
he declared him to have "approached as nearly to the ideal of a perfectly wise and virtuous man as
perhaps the nature of human frailty will permit."
Josiah Tucker, dean of Gloucester (d. 1799), holds a distinguished place among the immediate
predecessors of Smith. Most of his numerous productions had direct reference to contemporary
questions, and, though marked by much sagacity and penetration, are deficient in permanent
interest. In some of these he urged the impolicy of restrictions on the trade of Ireland, advocated a
union of that country with England, and recommended the recognition of the independence of the
United States of America. The most important of his general economic views are those relating to
international commerce. He is an ardent supporter of free-trade doctrines, which he bases on the
principles that there is between nations no necessary antagonism, but rather a harmony, of
interests, and that their several local advantages and different aptitudes naturally prompt them to
exchange. He had not, however, got quite clear of mercantilism, and favoured bounties on exported
manufactures and the encouragement of population by a tax on celibacy. Dupont, and after him
Blanqui, represent Tucker as a follower of the physiocrats, but there seems to be no ground for this
opinion except his agreement with them on the subject of the freedom of trade. Turgot translated
into French (1755), under the title of Questions Importantes sur le Commerce, a tract by Tucker on
The Expediency of a Law for the Naturalisation of Foreign Protestants.
In 1767 was published Sir James Steuart's Inquiry into the Principals of Political Economy. This was
one of the most unfortunate of books. It was the most complete and systematic survey of the
science irom the point of view of moderate mercantilism which had appeared in England. Steuart
was a man of no ordinary abilities, and had prepared himself for his task by long and serious study.
But the time for the mercantile doctrines was past, and the system of natural liberty was in
possession of an intellectual ascendency which foreshadowed its political triumph. Nine years later
the Wealth of Nations was given to the world, a work as superior to Steuart's in attractiveness of
style as in scientific soundness. Thus the latter was predestined to fail, and in fact never exercised
any considerable theoretic or practical influence. Smith never quotes or mentions it; being
acquainted with Steuart, whose conversation he said was better than his book, he probably wished
to keep clear of controversy with him.(21) The German economists have examined Steuart's treatise
more carefully than English writers have commonly done; and they recognise its high merits,
especially in relation to the theory of value and the subject of population. They have also pointed out
that, in the spirit of the best recent research, he has dwelt on the special characters which
distinguish the economies proper to different nations and different grades in social progress.
Coming now to the great name of Adam Smith (1723-1790), it is of the highest importance that we
should rightly understand his position and justly estimate his claims. It is plainly contrary to fact to
represent him, as some have done, as the creator of political economy. The subject of social wealth
had always in some degree, and increasingly in recent times, engaged the attention of philosophic
minds. The study had even indisputably assumed a systematic character, and, from being an
assemblage of fragmentary disquisitions on particular questions of national interest, had taken the
form, notably in Turgot's Réflexions, of an organised body of doctrine. The truth is, that Smith took
up the science when it was already considerably advanced; and it was this very circumstance which
enabled him, by the production of a classical treatise, to render most of his predecessors obsolete.
But, whilst all the economic labours of the preceding centuries prepared the way for him, they did
not anticipate his work. His appearance at an earlier stage, or without those previous labours, would
be inconceivable; but he built, on the foundation which had been laid by others, much of his own
that was precious and enduring.
Even those who do not fall into the error of making Smith the creator of the science, often separate
him too broadly from Quesnay and his followers, and represent the history of modern Economics as
consisting of the successive rise and reign of three doctrines -- the mercantile, the physiocratic, and
the Smithian. The last two are, it is true, at variance in some even important respects. But it is
evident, and Smith himself felt, that their agreements were much more fundamental than their
differences; and, if we regard them as historical forces, they must be considered as working towards
identical ends. They both urged society towards the abolition of the previously prevailing industrial
policy of European Governments; and their arguments against that policy rested essentially on the
same grounds. Whilst Smith's criticism was more searching and complete, he also analysed more
correctly than the physiocrats some classes of economic phenomena -- in particular dispelling the
illusions into which they had fallen with respect to the unproductive nature of manufactures and
commerce. Their school disappeared from the scientific field, not merely because it met with a
political check in the person of Turgot, but because, as we have already said, the Wealth of Nations
absorbed into itself all that was valuable in their teaching, whilst it continued more effectually the
impulse they had given to the necessary work of demolition.
The history of economic opinion in modern times, down to the third decade of the nineteenth
century, is, in fact, strictly bipartite. The first stage is filled with the mercantile system which, as we
have shown, was rather a practical policy than a speculative doctrine, and which came into
existence as the spontaneous growth of social conditions acting on minds not trained to scientific
habits. The second stage is occupied with the gradual rise and ultimate ascendency of another
system founded on the idea of the right of the individual to an unimpeded sphere for the exercise of
his economic activity. With the latter, which is best designated as the "system of natural liberty," we
ought to associate the memory of the physiocrats as well as that of Smith, without, however,
maintaining their services to have been equal to his.
The teaching of political economy was in the Scottish universities associated with that of moral
philosophy. Smith, as we are told, conceived the entire subject he had to treat in his public lectures
as divisible into four heads, the first of which was natural theology, the second ethics, the third
jurisprudence; whilst in the fourth "he examined those political regulations which are founded upon
expediency, and which are calculated to increase the riches, the power, and the prosperity of a
state." The last two branches of inquiry are regarded as forming but a single body of doctrine in the
well-known passage of the Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) in which the author promises to give
in another discourse "an account of the general principles of law and government, and of the
different revolutions they have undergone in the different ages and periods of society, not only in
what concerns justice, but in what concerts police, revenue, and arms, and whatever else is the
subject of law." This shows how little it was Smith's habit to separate (except provisionally), in his
conceptions or his researches, the economic phenomena of society from all the rest. The words
above quoted have, indeed, been not unjustly described as containing "an anticipation, wonderful
for his period, of general Sociology, both statical and dynamical, an anticipation which becomes still
more remarkable when we learn from his literary executors that he had formed the plan of a
connected history of the liberal sciences and elegant arts, which must have added to the branches
of social study already enumerated a view of the intellectual progress of society." Though these
large designs were never carried out in their integrity, as indeed at that period they could not have
been adequately realised, it has resulted from them that, though economic phenomena form the
special subject of the Wealth of Nations, Smith yet incorporated into that work much that relates to
the other social aspects, incurring thereby the censure of some of his followers, who insist with
pedantic narrowness on the strict isolation of the economic domain.
There has been much discussion on the question -- What is the scientific method followed by Smith
in his great work? By some it is considered to have been purely deductive, a view which Buckle has
perhaps carried to the greatest extreme. He asserts that in Scotland the inductive method was
unknown, that the inductive philosophy exercised no influence on Scottish thinkers; and, though
Smith spent some of the most important years of his youth in England, where the inductive method
was supreme, and though he was widely read in general philosophical literature, he yet thinks he
adopted the deductive method because it we habitually followed in Scotland, -- and this though
Buckle maintains that it is the only appropriate, or even possible, method in political economy, which
surely would have been a sufficient reason for choosing it. That the inductive spirit exercised no
influence on Scottish philosophers is certainly not true; as will be presently shown, Montesquieu,
whose method is essentially inductive, was in Smith's time studied with quite peculiar care and
regarded with special veneration by Smith's fellow-countrymen. As to Smith himself, what may justly
be said of him is that the deductive bent was certainly not the predominant character of his mind,
nor did his great excellence lie in the "dialectic skill" which Buckle ascribes to him. What strikes us
most in his book is his wide and keen observation of social facts, and his perpetual tendency to
dwell on these and elicit their significance, instead of drawing conclusions from abstract principles
by elaborate chains of reasoning. It is this habit of his mind which gives us, in reading him, so strong
and abiding a sense of being in contact with the realities of life.
That Smith does, however, largely employ the deductive method is certain; and that method is quite
legitimate when the premises from which the deduction sets out are known universal facts of human
nature and properties of external objects. Whether this mode of proceeding will carry us far may
indeed well be doubted; but its soundness cannot be disputed. But there is another vicious species
of deduction which, as Cliffe Leslie has shown, seriously tainted the philosophy of Smith -- in which
the premises are not facts ascertained by observation, but the same a priori assumptions, half
theological half metaphysical, respecting a supposed harmonious and beneficent natural order of
things which we found in the physiocrats, and which, as we saw, were embodied in the name of that
sect. In his view, Nature has made provision for social well-being by the principle of the human
constitution which prompts every man to better his condition: the individual aims only at his private
gain, but in doing so is "led by an invisible hand" to promote the public good, which was no part of
his intention; human institutions, by interfering with the action of this principle in the name of the
public interest, defeat their own end; but, when all systems of preference or restraint are taken
away," the obvious and simple system of natural liberty establishes itself of its own accord." This
theory is, of course, not explicitly presented by Smith as a foundation of his economic doctrines, but
it is really the secret substratum on which they rest. Yet, whilst such latent postulates warped his
view of things, they did not entirely determine his method. His native bent towards the study of
things as they are preserved him from extravagances into which many of his followers have fallen.
But besides this, as Leslie has pointed out, the influence of Montesquieu tended to counterbalance
the theoretic prepossessions produced by the doctrine of the jus naturae. That great thinker, though
he could not, at his period, understand the historical method which is truly appropriate to
sociological inquiry, yet founded his conclusions on induction. It is true, as Comte has remarked,
that his accumulation of facts, borrowed from the most different states of civilisation, and not
subjected to philosophic criticism, necessarily remained on the whole sterile, or at least could not
essentially advance the study of society much beyond the point at which he found it. His merit, as
we have before mentioned, lay in the recognition of the subjection of all social phenomena to natural
laws, not in the discovery of those laws. But this limitation was overlooked by the philosophers of the
time of Smith, who were much attracted by the system he followed of tracing social facts to the
special circumstances, physical or moral, of the communities in which they were observed. Leslie
has shown that Lord Kaimes, Dalrymple, and Millar -- contemporaries of Smith, and the last his pupil
-- were influenced by Montesquieu; and he might have added the more eminent name of Ferguson,
whose respect and admiration for the great Frenchman are expressed in striking terms in his History
of Civil Society.(22) We are even informed that Smith himself in his later years was occupied in
preparing a commentary on the Espirit des Lois.(23) he was thus affected by two different and
incongruous systems of thought -- one setting out from an imaginary code of nature intended for the
benefit of man, and leading to an optimistic view of the economic constitution founded on
enlightened self-interest; the other following inductive processes, and seeking to explain the several
states in which human societies are found existing, as results of circumstances or institutions which
have been in actual operation. And we find accordingly in his great work a combination of these two
methods -- inductive inquiry on the one hand, and, on the other a priori speculation founded on the
"Nature" hypothesis. The latter vicious proceeding has in some of his followers been greatly
aggravated, while the countervailing spirit of inductive investigation has fallen into the background,
and indeed the necessity or utility of any such investigation in the economic field has been
sometimes altogether denied.
Some have represented Smith's work as of so loose a texture and so defective an arrangement that
it may be justly described as consisting of a series of monographs. But this is certainly an
exaggeration. The book, it is true, is not framed on a rigid mould, nor is there any parade of
systematic divisions and subdivisions; and this doubtless recommended it to men of the world and
of business, for whose instruction it was, at least primarily intended. But it has the real and
pervading unity which results from a set of principles and a mode of thinking identical throughout
and the general absence of such contradictions as would arise from an imperfect digestion of the
subject.
Smith sets out from the thought that the annual labour of a nation is the source from which it derives
its supply of the necessaries and conveniences of life. He does not of course contemplate labour as
the only factor in production; but it has been supposed that by emphasising it at the outset he at
once strikes the note of difference between himself on the one hand and both the mercantilists and
the physiocrats on the other. The improvement in the productiveness of labour depends largely on
its division; and he proceeds accordingly to give his unrivalled exposition of that principle, of the
grounds on which it rests, and of its greater applicability to manufactures than to agriculture, in
consequence of which the latter relatively lags behind in the course of economic development.(24)
The origin of the division of labour he finds in the propensity of human nature "to truck, barter, or
exchange one thing for another." He shows that a certain accumulation of capital is a condition
precedent of this division, and that the degree to which it can be carried is dependent on the extent
of the market. When the division of labour has been established, each member of the society must
have recourse to the others for the supply of most of his wants; a medium of exchange is thus found
to be necessary, and money comes into use. The exchange of goods against each other or against
money gives rise to the notion of value. This word has two meanings -- that of utility, and that of
purchasing power; the one may be called value in use, the other value in exchange. Merely
mentioning the former, Smith goes on to study the latter. What, he asks, is the measure of value?
what regulates the amount of one thing which will be given for another? "Labour," Smith answers, "is
the real measure of the exchangeable value of all commodities." "Equal quantities of labour, at all
times and places, are of equal value to the labourer."(25) "Labour alone, therefore, never varying in
its own value, is alone the ultimate and real standard by which the value of all commodities can at
all times and places be estimated and compared. It is their real price; money is their nominal price
only." Money, however, is in men's actual transactions the measure of value, as well as the vehicle
of exchange; and the precious metals are best suited for this function, as varying little in their own
value for periods of moderate length; for distant times, corn is a better standard of comparison. In
relation to the earliest social stage, we need consider nothing but the amount of labour employed in
the production of an article as determining its exchange value; but in more advanced periods price
is complex, and consists in the most general case of three elements -- wages, profit, and rent.
Wages are the reward of labour. Profit arises as soon as stock, being accumulated in the hands of
one person, is employed by him in setting others to work, and supplying them with materials and
subsistence, in order to make a gain by what they produce. Rent arises as soon as the land of a
country has all become private property; "the landlords, like all other men, love to reap where they
never sowed, and demand a rent even for its natural produce." In every improved society, then,
these three elements enter more or less into the price of the far greater part of commodities. There
is in every society or neighbourhood an ordinary or average rate of wages and profit in every
different employment of labour and stock, regulated by principles to be explained hereafter, as also
an ordinary or average rate of rent. These may be called the natural rates at the time when and the
place where they prevail; and the natural price of a commodity is what is sufficient to pay for the rent
of the land,(26) the wages of the labour, and the profit of the stock necessary for bringing the
commodity to market. The market price may rise above or fall below the amount so fixed, being
determined by the proportion between the quantity brought to market and the demand of those who
are willing to pay the natural price. Towards the natural price as a centre the market price, regulated
by competition, constantly gravitates. Some commodities, however, are subject to a monopoly of
production, whether from the peculiarities of a locality or from legal privilege their price is always the
highest that can be got; the natural price of other commodities is the lowest which can be taken for
any length of time together. The three component parts or factors of price vary with the
circumstances of the society. The rate of wages is determined by a "dispute" or struggle of opposite
interests between the employer and the workman. A minimum rate is fixed by the condition that they
must be at least sufficient to enable a man and his wife to maintain themselves and, in general,
bring up a family. The excess above this will depend on the circumstances of the country and the
consequent demand for labour -- wages being high when national wealth is increasing, low when it
is declining. The same circumstances determine the variation of profits, but in an opposite direction;
the increase of stock, which raises wages, tending to lower profit through the mutual competition of
capitalists. "The whole of the advantages and disadvantages of the different employments of labour
and stock must, in the same neighbourhood, be either perfectly equal or continually tending to
equality"; if one had greatly the advantage over the others, people would crowd into it, and the level
would soon be restored. Yet pecuniary wages and profits are very different in different employment
-- either from certain circumstances affecting the employments, which recommend or disparage
them in men's notions, or from national policy, "which nowhere leaves things at perfect liberty." Here
follows Smith's admirable exposition of the causes which produce the inequalities in wages and
profits just referred to, a passage affording ample evidence of his habits of nice observation of the
less obvious traits in human nature, and also of the operation both of these and of social institutions
on economic facts. The rent of land comes next to be considered, as the last of the three elements
of price. Rent is a monopoly price, equal, not to what the landlord could afford to take, but to what
the farmer can afford to give, "Such parts only of the produce of land can commonly be brought to
market, of which the ordinary price is sufficient to replace the stock which must be employed in
bringing them thither, together with the ordinary profits. If the ordinary price is more than this; the
surplus part will naturally go to the rent of the land. If it is not more, though the commodity may be
brought to market, it can afford no rent to the landlord, Whether the price is or is not more depends
on the demand." "Rent, therefore, enters into the price of commodities in a different way from wages
and profits. High or low wages and profit are the causes of high or low price; high or low rent is the
effect of it."
Rent, wages, and profits, as they are the elements of price, are also the constituents of income; and
the three great orders of every civilised society, from whose revenues that of every other order is
ultimately derived, are the landlords, the labourers, and the capitalists. The relation of the interests
of these three classes to those of society at large is different. The interest of the landlord always
coincides with the general interest: whatever promotes or obstructs the one has the same effect on
the other. So also does that of the labourer: when the wealth of the nation is progressive, his wages
are high; they are low when it is stationary or retrogressive. "The interest of the third order has not
the same connection with the general interest of the society as that of the other two;... it is always in
some respects different from and opposite to that of the public."
The subject of the second book is "the nature, accumulation, and improvement of stock." A man's
whole stock consists of two portions -- that which is reserved for his immediate consumption, and
that which is employed so as to yield a revenue to its owner. This latter, which is his "capital," is
divisible into the two classes of "fixed" and "circulating." The first is such as yields a profit without
passing into other hands. The second consists of such goods, raised, manufactured, or purchased,
as are sold for a profit and replaced by other goods; this sort of capital is therefore constantly going
from and returning to the hands of its owner, The whole capital of a society falls under the same two
heads. Its fixed capital consists chiefly of (1) machines, (2) buildings which are the means of
procuring a revenue, (3) agricultural improvements, and (4) the acquired and useful abilities of all
members of the society (since sometimes known as "personal capital"). Its circulating capital is also
composed of four parts -- (1) money, (2) provisions in the hands of the dealers, (3) materials, and
(4) completed work in the hands of the manufacturer or merchant. Next comes the distinction of the
gross national revenue from the net -- the first being the whole produce of the land and labour of a
country, the second what remains after deducting the expense of maintaining the fixed capital of the
country and that part of its circulating capital which consists of money. Money, "the great wheel of
circulation," is altogether different from the goods which are circulated by means of it; it is a costly
instrument by means of which all that each individual receives is distributed to him; and the
expenditure required, first to provide it, and afterwards to maintain it, is a deduction from the net
revenue of the society. In development of this consideration, Smith goes on to explain the gain to
the community arising from the substitution of paper money for that composed of the precious
metals; and here occurs the remarkable illustration in which the use of gold and silver money is
compared to a highway on the ground, that of paper money to a waggon-way through the air. In
proceeding to consider the accumulation of capital, he is led to the distinction between productive
and unproductive labour -- the former being that which is fixed or realised in a particular object or
vendible article, the latter that which is not so realised. The former is exemplified in the labour of the
manufacturing workman, the latter in that of the menial servant. A broad line of demarcation is thus
drawn between the labour which results in commodities or increased value of commodities and that
which does no more than render services: the former is productive, the latter unproductive.
"Productive" is by no means equivalent to "useful": the labours of the magistrate, the soldier, the
churchman, lawyer, and physician are, in Smith's sense, unproductive. Productive labourers alone
are employed out of capital; unproductive labourers, as well as those who do not labour at all, are all
maintained by revenue. In advancing industrial communities, the portion of annual produce set apart
as capital bears an increasing proportion to that which is immediately destined to constitute a
revenue, either as rent or as profit. Parsimony is the source of the increase of capital; by
augmenting the fund devoted to the maintenance of productive hands, it puts in motion an additional
quantity of industry, which adds to the value of the annual produce. What is annually saved is as
regularly consumed as what is spent, but by a different set of persons, by productive labourers
instead of idlers or unproductive labourers; and the former reproduce with a profit the value of their
consumption. The prodigal, encroaching on his capital, diminishes, as far as in him lies, the amount
of productive labour, and so the wealth of the country; nor is this result affected by his expenditure
being on home-made, as distinct from foreign, commodities. Every prodigal, therefore, is a public
enemy; every frugal man a public benefactor. The only mode of increasing the annual produce of
the land and labour is to increase either the number of productive labourers or the productive
powers of those labourers. Either process will in general require additional capital, the former to
maintain the new labourers, the latter to provide improved machinery or to enable the employer to
introduce a more complete division of labour. In what are commonly called loans of money, it is not
really the money, but the money's worth, that the borrower wants; and the lender really assigns to
him the right to a certain portion of the annual produce of the land and labour of the country. As the
general capital of a country increases, so also does the particular portion of it from which the
possessors wish to derive a revenue without being at the trouble of employing it themselves; and, as
the quantity of stock thus available for loans is augmented, the interest diminishes, not merely "from
the general causes which make the market price of things commonly diminish as their quantity
increases," but because, with the increase of capital, "it becomes gradually wore and more difficult
to find within the country a profitable method of employing any new capital" -- whence arises a
competition between different capitals, and a lowering of profits, which must diminish the price
which can be paid for the use of capital, or in other words the rate of interest. It was formerly wrongly
supposed, and even Locke and Montesquieu did not escape this error, that the fall in the value of
the precious metals consequent on the discovery of the American mines was the real cause of the
permanent lowering of the rate of interest in Europe. But this view, already refuted by Hume, is
easily seen to be erroneous. "In some countries the interest of money has been prohibited by law.
But, as something can everywhere be made by the use of money, something ought everywhere to
be paid for the use of it," and will in fact be paid for it; and the prohibition will only heighten the evil
of usury by increasing the risk to the lender. The legal rate should be a very little above the lowest
market rate; sober people will then be preferred as borrowers to prodigals and projectors, who at a
higher legal rate would have an advantage over them, being alone willing to offer that higher rate.
(27)
As to the different employments of capital, the quantity of productive labour put in motion by an
equal amount varies extremely according as that amount is employed -- (1) in the improvement of
lands, mines, or fisheries, (2) in manufactures, (3) in wholesale or (4) retail trade. In agriculture
"Nature labours along with man," and not only the capital of the farmer is reproduced with his profits,
but also the rent of the landlord. It is therefore the employment of a given capital which is most
advantageous to society. Next, in order come manufactures; then wholesale trade -- first the home
trade, secondly the foreign trade of consumption, last the carrying trade. All these employments of
capital, however, are not only advantageous, but necessary, and will introduce themselves in the
due degree, if they are left to the spontaneous action of individual enterprise.
These first two books contain Smith's general economic scheme; and we have stated it as fully as
was consistent with the necessary brevity, because from this formulation of doctrine the English
classical school set out, and round it the discussions of more recent times in different countries have
in a great measure revolved. Some of the criticisms of his successors and their modifications of his
doctrines will come under our notice as we proceed.
The critical philosophers of the eighteenth century were often destitute of the historical spirit, which
was no part of the endowment needed for their principal social office. But some of the most eminent
of them, especially in Scotland, showed a marked capacity and predilection for historical studies.
Smith was amongst the latter; Knies and others justly remark on the masterly sketches of this kind
which occur in the Wealth of Nations. The longest and most elaborate of these occupies the third
book; it is an account of the course followed by the nations of modern Europe in the successive
development of the several forms of industry. It affords a curious example of the effect of doctrinal
prepossessions in obscuring the results of historical inquiry. Whilst he correctly describes the
European movement of industry, and explains it as arising out of adequate social causes, he yet, in
accordance with the absolute principles which tainted his philosophy, protests against it as involving
an entire inversion of the "natural order of things." First agriculture, then manufactures, lastly foreign
commerce; any other order than this he considers "unnatural and retrograde." Hume, a more purely
positive thinker, simply sees the facts, accepts them, and classes them under a general law. "It is a
violent method," he says, "and in most cases impracticable, to oblige the labourer to toil in order to
raise from the land more than what subsists himself and family. Furnish him with manufactures and
commodities, and he will do it of himself." "If we consult history, we shall find that, in most nations,
foreign trade has preceded any refinement in home manufactures, and given birth to domestic
luxury."
The fourth book is principally devoted to the elaborate and exhaustive polemic against the
mercantile system which finally drove it from the field of science, and has exercised a powerful
influence on economic legislation. When protection is now advocated, it is commonly on different
grounds from those which were in current use before the time of Smith. He believed that to look for
the restoration of freedom of foreign trade in Great Britain would have been "as absurd as to expect
that an Oceana or Utopia should be established in it"; yet, mainly in consequence of his labours,
that object has been completely attained; and it has lately been said with justice that free trade
might have been more generally accepted by other nations if the patient reasoning of Smith had not
been replaced by dogmatism. His teaching on the subject is not altogether unqualified; but, on the
whole, with respect to exchanges of every kind, where economic motives alone enter, his voice is in
favour of freedom. He has regard, however, to political as well as economic interests, and on the
ground that "defence is of much more importance than opulence", pronounces the Navigation Act to
have been "perhaps the wisest of all the commercial regulations of England." Whilst objecting to the
prevention of the export of wool, he proposes a tax on that export as somewhat less injurious to the
interest of growers than the prohibition, whilst it would "afford a sufficient advantage" to the domestic
over the foreign manufacturer. This is, perhaps, his most marked deviation from the rigour of
principle; it was doubtless a concession to popular opinion with a view to an attainable practical
improvement The wisdom of retaliation in order to procure the repeal of high duties or prohibitions
imposed by foreign Governments depends, he says, altogether on the likelihood of its success in
effecting the object aimed at, but he does not conceal his contempt for the practice of such
expedients. The restoration of freedom in any manufacture, when it has grown to considerable
dimensions by means of high duties, should, he thinks, from motives of humanity, be brought about
only by degrees and with circumspection, -- though the amount of evil which would be caused by the
immediate abolition of the duties is, in his opinion, commonly exaggerated. The case in which J. S.
Mill would tolerate protection -- that, namely, in which an industry well adapted to a country is kept
down by the acquired ascendency of foreign producers -- is referred to by Smith; but he is opposed
to the admission of this exception for reasons which do not appear to be conclusive.(28) He is
perhaps scarcely consistent in approving the concession of temporary monopolies to joint-stock
companies undertaking risky enterprises "of which the public is afterwards to reap the benefit."(29)
He is less absolute in his doctrine of Governmental noninterference when he comes to consider in
his fifth book the "expenses of the sovereign or the commonwealth." He recognises as coming
within the functions of the state the erection and maintenance of those public institutions and public
works which, though advantageous to the society, could not repay, and therefore must not be
thrown upon, individuals or small groups of individuals. He remarks in a just historical spirit that the
performance of these functions requires very different degrees of expense in the different periods of
society. Besides the institutions and works intended for public defence and the administration of
justice, and those required for facilitating the commerce of the society, he considers those
necessary for promoting the instruction of the people. He thinks the public at large may with
propriety not only facilitate and encourage, but even impose upon almost the whole body of the
people, the acquisition in youth of the most essential elements of education. He suggests as the
mode of enforcing this obligation the requirement of submission to a test examination "before any
one could obtain the freedom in any corporation, or be allowed to set up a trade in any village or
town corporate." Similarly, he is of opinion that some probation, even in the higher and more difficult
sciences, might be enforced as a condition of exercising any liberal profession, or becoming a
candidate for any honourable office. The expense of the institutions for religious instruction as well
as for general education, he holds, may without injustice be defrayed out of the funds of the whole
society, though he would apparently prefer that it should be met by ihe voluntary contributions of
those who think they have occasion for such education or instruction. There is much that is sound,
as well as interesting and suggestive, in this fifth book, in which he shows a political instinct and a
breadth of view by which he is favourably contrasted with the Manchester school. But, if we may say
so without disrespect to so great a man, there are traces in it of what is now called Philistinism -- a
low view of the ends of art and poetry -- which arose perhaps in part from personal defect; and a
certain deadness to the high aims and perennial importance of religion, which was no doubt chiefly
due to the influences of an age when the critical spirit was doing an indispensable work, in the
performance of which thr transitory was apt to be confounded with the permanent.
For the sake of considering as a whole Smith's view of the functions of government, we have
postponed noticing his treatment of the physiocratic system, which occupies a part of his fourth
book. He had formed the acquaintance of Quesnay, Turgot, and other members of their group
during his sojourn in France in 1765, and would, as he told Dugald Stewart, had the patriarch of the
school lived long enough, have dedicated to him the Wealth of Nations. He declares that, with all its
imperfections, the system of Quesnay is "perhaps the nearest approximation to the truth that had yet
appeared on the subject of political economy." Yet he seems not to be adequately conscious of the
degree of coincidence between his own doctrines and those of the physiocrats. Dupont de Nemours
complained that he did not do Quesnay the justice of recognising him as his spiritual father. it is,
however, alleged, on the other side, that already in 1753 Smith had been teaching as professor a
body of economic doctrine the same in its broad features with that contained in his great work. This
is indeed said by Stewart; and, though he gives no evidence of it, it is possibly quite true; if so,
Smith's doctrinal descent must be traced rather from Hume than from the French school. The
principal error of this school, that, namely, of representing agricultural labour as alone productive, he
refutes in the fourth book, though in a manner which has not always been considered effective.
Traces of the influence of their mistaken view appear to remain in his own work, as, for example, his
assertion that in agriculture nature labours along with man, whilst in manufactures nature does
nothing, man does all; and his distinction between productive and unproductive labour, which was
doubtless suggested by their use of those epithets, and which is scarcely consistent with his
recognition of what is now called "personal capital." To the same source M'Culloch and others refer
the origin of Smith's view, which they represent as an obvious error, that "individual advantage is not
always a true test of the public advantageousness of different employments." But that view is really
quite correct, as Professor Nicholson has clearly shown.(30) That the form taken by the use of
capital, profits being given, is not indifferent to the working class as a whole even Ricardo admitted;
and Cairnes, as we shall see, built or this consideration some of the most far-reaching conclusions
in his Leading Principles.
On Smiths theory of taxation in his fifth book it is not necessary for us to dwell. The well-known
canons which he lays down as prescribing the essentials of a good system have been generally
accepted. They have lately been severely criticised by Professor Walker--of whose objections,
however, there is only one which appears to be well founded. Smith seems to favour the view that
the contribution of the individual to public expenses may be regarded as payment for the services
rendered to him by the state, and ought to be proportional to the extent of those services. If he held
this opinion, which some of his expressions imply, he was certainly so far wrong in principle.
We shall not be held to anticipate unduly if we remark here on the way in which opinion, revolted by
the aberrations of some of Smiths successors, has tended to turn from the disciples to the master. A
strong sense of his comparative freedom from the vicious tendencies of Ricardo and his followers
has recently prompted the suggestion that we ought now to recur to Smith, and take up once more
from him the line of the economical succession. But notwithstanding his indisputable superiority,
and whilst fully recognising the great services rendered by his immortal work, we must not forget
that, as has been already said, that work was, on the whole, a product, though an exceptionally
eminent one, of the negative philosophy of the 18th century, resting largely in its ultimate foundation
on metaphysical bases. The mind of Smith was mainly occupied with the work of criticism so urgent
in his time ; his principal task was to discredit and overthrow the economic system then prevalent,
and to demonstrate the radical unfitness of the existing European Governments to direct the
industrial movement. This office of his fell in with, and formed a part of, the general work of
demolition carried on by the thinkers who gave to his period its characteristic tone. It is to his honour
that, besides this destructive operation, he contributed valuable elements to the preparation of an
organic system of thought and of life. In his special domain he has not merely extinguished many
errors and prejudices, and cleared the ground for truth, but has left us a permanent possession in
the judicious analyses of economic facts and ideas, the wise practical suggestions, and the
luminous indications of all kinds with which his work abounds. Belonging to the best philosophical
school of his period, that with which the names of Hume and Diderot are associated, he tended
strongly towards the positive point of view. But it was not possible for him to attain it; and the final
and fully normal treatment of the economic life of societies must be constituted on other and more
lasting foundations than those which underlie his imposing construction.
It has been well said that of philosophic doctrines the saying "By their fruits ye shall know them" is
eminently true. And it cannot be doubted that the germs of the vicious methods and false or
exaggerated theories of Smiths successors are to be found in his own work, though his good sense
and practical bent prevented his following out his principles to their extreme consequences. The
objections of Hildebrand and others to the entire historical development of doctrine which the
Germans designate as "Smithianismus" are regarded by those critics as applicable, not merely to
his school as a whole, but, though in a less degree, to himself. The following are the most important
of these objections. It is said--(1) Smiths conception of the social economy is essentially
individualistic. In this he falls in with the general character of the negative philosophy of his age.
That philosophy, in its most typical forms, even denied the natural existence of the disinterested
affections, and explained the altruistic feelings as secondary results of self-love. Smith, however,
like Hume, rejected these extreme views; and hence it has been held that in the Wealth of Nations
he consciously, though tacitly, abstracted from the benevolent principles in human nature, and as a
logical artifice supposed an "economic man" actuated by purely selfish motives. However this may
be, he certainly places himself habitually at the point of view of the individual, whom he treats as a
purely egoistic force, working uniformly in the direction of private gain, without regard to the good of
others or of the community at large. (2) He justifies this personal attitude by its consequences,
presenting the optimistic view that the good of the community is best attained through the free play
of individual cupidities, provided only that the law prevents the interference of one member of the
society with the self-seeking action of another. He assumes with the negative school at large-though
he has passages which are not in harmony with these propositions -- that every one knows his true
interest and will pursue it, and that the economic advantage of the individual coincides with that of
the society. To this last conclusion he is secretly led, as we have seen, by a priori theological ideas,
and also by metaphysical conceptions of a supposed system of nature, natural right, and natural
liberty. (3) By this reduction of almost every question to one of individual gain, he is led to a too
exclusive consideration of exchange value as distinct from wealth in the proper sense. This, whilst
lending a mechanical facility in arriving at conclusions, gives a superficial character to economic
investigations, divorcing it from the physical and biological sciences, excluding the question of real
social utility, leaving no room for a criticism of production, and leading to a denial, like J. S. Mill's, of
any economic doctrine dealing with consumption -- in other words, with the use of wealth. (4) In
condemning the existing industrial policy, he tends too much towards a glorification of non-
government and a repudiation of all social intervention for the regulation of economic life. (5) He
does not keep in view the moral destination of our race, nor regard wealth as a means to the higher
ends of life, and thus incurs, not altogether unjustly, the charge of materialism, in the wider sense of
that word. Lastly, (6) his whole system is too absolute in its character; it does not sufficiently
recognie the fact that, in the language of Hildebrand, man, as a member of society, is a child of
civilization and a product of history, and that account ought to be taken of the different stages of
social development as implying altered economic conditions and calling for altered economic action,
or even involving a modification of the actor. Perhaps in all the respects here enumerated, certainly
in some of them, and notably in the last, Smith is less open to criticism than most of the later English
economists; but it must, we think, be admitted that to the general principles which lie at the basis of
his scheme the ultimate growth of these several vicious tendencies is traceable.
Great expectations had been entertained respecting Smith's work by competent judges before its
publication, as is shown by the language of Ferguson on the subject in his History of Civil Society.
(31) That its merits received prompt recognition is proved by the fact of six editions having been
called for within the fifteen years after its appearance.(32) From the year 1783 it was more and more
quoted in Parliament. Pitt was greatly impressed by its reasonings; Smith is reported to have said
that that Minister understood the book as well as himself, Pulteney said in 1797 that Smith would
persuade the then living generation and would govern the next.(33)
Smith's earliest critics were Bentham and Lauderdale, who, though in general agreement with him,
differed on special points. Jeremy Bentham was author of a short treatise entitled A Manuel of
Political Economy and various economic monographs, the most celebrated of which was his
Defence of Usury (1787). This contained (Letter xiii) an elaborate criticism of a passage in the
Wealth of Nations, already cited, in which Smith had approved of a legal maximum rate of interest
fixed but a very little above the lowest market rate, as tending to throw the capital of the country into
the hands of sober persons, as opposed to "prodigals and projectors." Smith is said to have
admitted that Bentham had made out his case. He certainly argues it with great ability;(34) and the
true doctrine no doubt is that, in a developed industrial society, it is expedient to let the rate be fixed
by contract between the lender and the borrower, the law interfering only in case of fraud.
Bentham's main significance does not belong to the economic field. But, on the one hand, what is
known as Benthamism was undoubtedly, as Comte has said,(35)a derivative from political
economy, and in particular from the system of natural liberty; and, on the other, it promoted the
temporary ascendency of that system by extending to the whole of social and moral theory the use
of the principle of individual interest and the method of deduction from that interest. This alliance
between political economy and the scheme of Bentham is seen in the personal group of thinkers
which formed itself round him, -- thinkers most inaptly characterised by J. S. Mill as "profound," but
certainly possessed of much acuteness and logical power, and tending, though vaguely, towards a
positive sociology, which, from their want of genuinely scientific culture and their absolute modes of
thought, they were incapable of founding.
Lord Lauderdale, in his Inquiry into the Nature and Origin of Public Wealth (1804), a book still worth
reading, pointed out certain real weaknesses in Smith's account of value and the measure of value,
and of the productivity of labour, and threw additional light on several subjects, such as the true
mode of estimating the national income, and the reaction of the distribution of wealth on its
production.
Smith stood just at the beginning of a great industrial revolution . The world of production and
commerce in which he lived was still, as Cliffe Leslie has said, a "very early" and comparatively
narrow one; "the only steam-engine he refers to is Newcomen's," and the cotton trade is mentioned
by him only once, and that incidentally. "Between the years 1760 and 1770," says Mr. Marshall,
"Roebuck began to smelt iron by coal, Brindley connected the rising seats of manufactures with the
sea by canals, Wedgwood discovered the art of making earthenware cheaply and well, Hargreaves
invented the spinning-jenny, Arkwright utilised Wyatt's and High's inventions for spinning by rollers
and applied water-power to move them, and Watt invented the condensing steam-engine.
Crompton's mule and Cartwright's power-loom came shortly after." Out of this rapid evolution
followed a vast expansion of industry, but also many deplorable results, which, had Smith been able
to foresee them, might have made him a less enthusiastic believer in the benefits to be wrought by
the mere liberation of effort, and a less vehement denouncer of old institutions which in their day
had given a partial protection to labour. Alongside of these evils of the new industrial system,
Socialism appeared as the alike inevitable and indispensable expression of the protest of the
working classes and the aspiration after a better order of things; and what we now call "the social
question," that inexorable problem of modern life, rose into the place which it has ever since
maintained. This question was first effectually brought before the English mind by Thomas Robert
Malthus (1766-1834), not, however, under the impulse of revolutionary sympathies, but in the
interests of a conservative policy.
The first edition of the work which achieved this result appeared anonymously in 1798 under the title
-- An Essay on the Principle of Population, as it affects the future improvement of Society, with
remarks on the speculations of Mr Godwin, M. Condorcet, and other writers. This book arose out of
certain private controversies of its author with his father, Daniel Malthus, who had been a friend of
Rousseau, and was an ardent believer in the doctrine of human progress as preached by Condorcet
and other French thinkers and by their English disciples. The most distinguished of the latter was
William Godwin, whose Enquiry concerning Political Justice had been published in 1793. The views
put forward in that work had been restated by its author in the Enquirer (1797), and it was on the
essay in this volume entitled "Avarice and Profusion" that the discussion between the father and the
son arose, "the general question of the future improvement of society" being thus raised between
them -- the elder Malthus defending the doctrines of Godwin, and the younger assailing them. The
latter "sat down with an intention of merely stating his thoughts on paper in a clearer manner than he
thought he could do in conversation," and the Essay on population was the result.
The social scheme of Godwin was founded on the idea that the evils of society arise from the vices
of human institutions. There is more than enough of wealth available for all, but it is not equally
shared: one has too much, another has little or nothing. Let this wealth, as well as the labour of
producing it, be equally divided; then every one will by moderate exertion obtain sufficient for plain
living; there will be abundant leisure, which will be spent in intellectual and moral self-improvement;
reason will determine human actions; government and every kind of force will be unnecessary; and,
in time, by the peaceful influence of truth, perfection and happiness will be established on earth. To
these glowing anticipations Malthus opposes the facts of the necessity of food and the tendency of
mankind to increase up to the limit of the available supply of it. In a state of universal physical well-
being, this tendency, which in real life is held in check by the difficulty of procuring a subsistence,
would operate without restraint. Scarcity would follow the increase of numbers; the leisure would
soon cease to exist; the old struggle for life would recommence; and inequality would reign once
more. If Godwin's ideal system, therefore, could be established, the single force ot the principle of
population, Malthus maintained, would suffice to break it down.
It will be seen that the essay was written with a polemical object; it was an occasional pamphlet
directed against the utopias of the day, not at all a systematic treatise on population suggested by a
purely scientific interest. As a polemic, it was decidedly successful; it was no difficult task to dispose
of the scheme of equality propounded by Godwin. Already, in 1761, Dr. Robert Wallace had
published a work (which was amongst those used by Malthus in the composition of his essay)
entitled Various Prospects of Mankind, Nature, and Providence, in which, after speaking of a
community of goods as a remedy for the ills of society, he confessed that he saw one fatal objection
to such a social organization, namely, "the excessive population that would ensue." With
Condorcet's extravagances, too, Malthus easily dealt. That eminent man, amidst the tempest of the
French Revolution, had written, whilst in hiding from his enemies, his Esquisse d'un tableau
historique de l'esprit humain. The general conception of this book makes its appearance an epoch
in tht history of the rise of sociology. In it, if we except some partial sketches by Turgot,(36) is for the
first time explained the idea of a theory of social dynamics founded on history; and its author is on
this ground recognized by Comte as his principal immediate predecessor. But in the execution of his
great project Condorcet failed. His negative metaphysics prevent his justly appreciating the past,
and he indulges, at the close of his work, in vague hypotheses respecting the perfectibility of our
race, and in irrational expectations of an indefinite extension of the duration of human life. Malthus
seems to have little sense of the nobleness of Condorcet's attitude, and no appreciation of the
grandeur of his leading idea. But of his chimerical hopes he is able to make short work; his good
sense, if somewhat limited and prosaic, is at least effectual in detecting and exposing utopias.
The project of a formal and detailed treatise on population was an after-thought of Malthus. The
essay in which he had studied a hypothetic future led him to examine the effects of the principle he
had put forward on the past and present state of society; and he undertook an historical examination
of these effects, and sought to draw such inferences in relation to the actual state of things as
experience seemed to warrant. The consequence of this was such a change in the nature and
composition of the essay as made it, in his own language, "a new work." The book, so altered,
appeared in 1803 under the title, An Essay on the Principle of Population, or a View of its Past and
Present Effects on Human Happiness; with an Enquiry into our prospects respecting the future
removal or mitigation of the evils which it occasions.
In the original form of the essay he had spoken of no checks to population but those which came
under the head either of vice or of misery. He now introduces the new element of the preventive
check supplied by what he calls "moral restraint," and is thus enabled, as he himself said, to "soften
some of the harshest conclusions" at which he had before arrived. The treatise passed through five
editions(37) in his lifetime, and in all of them he introduced various additions and corrections. That
of 1817 is the last he fully revised, and presents the text substantially as it has since been reprinted.
Notwithstanding the great development which he gave to his work, and the almost unprecedented
amount of discussion to which it gave rise, it remains a matter of some difficulty to discover what
solid contribution he has made to our knowledge, nor is it easy to ascertain precisely what practical
precepts, not already familiar, he founded on his theoretic principles. This twofold vagueness is well
brought out in his celebrated correspondence with Senior, in the course of which it seems to be
made apparent that his doctrine is new not so much in its essence as in the phraseology in which it
is couched. He himself tells us that when, after the publication of the original essay, the main
argument of which he had deduced from Hume, Wallace, Adam Smith, and Price, he began to
inquire more closely into the subject, he found that "much more had been done" upon it "than he
had been aware of." It had "been treated in such a manner by some of the French economists,
occasionally by Montesquieu, and, among our own writers, by Dr. Franklin, Sir James Steuart, Mr.
Arthur Young, and Mr. Townsend, as to create a natural surprise that it had not excited more of the
public attention." "Much, however," he thought, "remained yet to be done. The comparison between
the increase of population and food had not, perhaps, been stated with sufficient force and
precision," and "few inquiries had been made into the various modes by which the level" between
population and the means of subsistence "is effected." The first desideratum here mentioned -- the
want, namely, of an accurate statement of the relation between the increase of population and that
of food -- Malthus doubtless supposed to have been supplied by the celebrated proposition that
"population increases in a geometrical, food in an arithmetical, ratio." This proposition, however, has
been conclusively shown to be erroneous, there being no such difference of law between the
increase of man and that of the organic beings which form his food. J. S. Mill is indignant with those
who criticise Malthus's formula, which he groundlessly describes as a mere "passing remark,"
because, as he thinks, though erroneous, it sufficiently suggests what is true; but it is surely
important to detect unreal science, and to test strictly the foundations of beliefs. When the formula
which we have cited is not used, other somewhat nebulous expressions are frequently employed,
as, for example, that "population has a tendency to increase faster than food," a sentence in which
both are treated as if they were spontaneous growths, and which on account of the ambiguity of the
word "tendency," is admittedly consistent with the fact asserted by Senior, that food tends to
increase faster than population. It must always have been perfectly well known that population will
probably (though not necessarily) increase with every augmentation of the supply of subsistence,
and may, in some instances, inconveniently press upon, or even for a certain time exceed, the
number properly corresponding to that supply. Nor could it ever have been doubted that war,
disease, poverty -- the last two often the consequences of vice -- are causes which keep population
down. In fact, the way in which abundance, increase of numbers, want, increase of deaths, succeed
each other in the natural economy, when reason does not intervene, had been fully explained by the
Rev. Joseph Townsend in his Dissertation on the Poor Laws (1786), which, we have seen, was
known to Malthus. Again, it is surely plain enough that the apprehension by individuals of the evils of
poverty, or a sense of duty to their possible offspring, may retard the increase of population, and has
in all civilized communities operated to a certain extent in that way. It is only when such obvious
truths are clothed in the technical terminology of "positive" and "preventive checks" that they appear
novel and profound; and yet they appear to contain the whole message of Malthus to mankind. The
laborious apparatus of historical and statistical facts respecting the several countries of the globe,
adduced in the altered form of the essay, though it contains a good deal that is curious and
interesting, establishes no general result which was not previously well known, and is accordingly
ignored by James Mill and others, who rest the theory on facts patent to universal observation.
Indeed, as we have seen, the entire historical inquiry was an afterthought of Malthus, who, before
entering on it, had already announced his fundamental principle.
It would seem, then, that what has been ambitiously called Malthus's theory of population, instead of
being a great discovery, as some have represented it, or a poisonous novelty, as others have
considered it, is no more than a formal enunciation of obvious, though sometimes neglected, facts.
The pretentious language often applied to it by economists is objectionable, as being apt to make us
forget that the whole subject with which it deals is as yet very imperfectly understood -- the causes
which modify the force of the sexual instinct, and those which lead to variations in fecundity, still
awaiting a complete investigation.(38)
It is the law of diminishing returns from land (of which more will be said hereafter), involving as it
does -- though only hypothetically -- the prospect of a continuously increasing difficulty in obtaining
the necessary sustenance for all the members of a society, that gives the principal importance to
population as an economic factor. It is, in fact, the confluence of the Malthusian ideas with the
theories of Ricardo, especially with the corollaries which the latter, as we shall see, deduced from
the doctrine of rent (though these were not accepted by Malthus), that has led to the introduction of
population as an element in the discussion of so many economic questions in recent times.
Malthus had undoubtedly the great merit of having called public attention in a striking and
impressive way to a subject which had neither theoretically nor practically been sufficiently
considered. But he and his followers appear to have greatly exaggerated both the magnitude and
the urgency of the dangers to which they pointed.(39) In their conceptions a single social
imperfection assumed such portentous dimensions than it seemed to overcloud the whole heaven
and threaten the world with ruin. This doubtless arose from his having at first omitted altogether from
his view of the question the great counteracting agency of moral restraint. Because a force exists,
capable, if unchecked, of producing certain results, it does not follow that those results are imminent
or even possible in the sphere of experience. A body thrown from the hand would, under the single
impulse of projection, move for ever in a straight line; but it would not be reasonable to take special
action for the prevention of this result, ignoring the fact that it will be sufficiently counteracted by the
other forces which will come into play. And such other forces exist in the case we are considering. If
the inherent energy of the principle of population (supposed everywhere the same) is measured by
the rate at which numbers increase under the most favourable circumstances, surely the force of
less favourable circumstances, acting through prudential or altruistic motives, is measured by the
great difference between this maximum rate and those which are observed to prevail in most
European countries. Under a rational system of institutions, the adaptation of numbers to the means
available for their support is effected by the felt or anticipated pressure of circumstances and the
fear of social degradation, within a tolerable degree of approximation to what is desirable. To bring
the result nearer to the just standard, a higher measure of popular enlightenment and more serious
habits of moral reflection ought indeed to be encouraged. But it is the duty of the individual to his
actual or possible offspring, and not any vague notions as to the pressure of the national population
on subsistence, that will be adequate to influence conduct.
The only obligation on which Malthus insists is that of abstinence from marriage so long as the
necessary provision for a family has not been acquired or cannot be reasonably anticipated. The
idea of post-nuptial continence, which has since been put forward by J. S. Mill and others, is foreign
to his view. He even suggests that an allowance might be made from the pubic funds for every child
in a family beyond the number of six, on the ground that, when a man marries, he cannot tell how
many children he shall have, and that the reief from an unlooked-for distress afforded by such a
grant would not operate as an encouragement to marriage. The duty of economic prudence in
entering on the married state is plain; but in the case of working men the idea of a secured provision
must not be unduly pressed, and it must also be remembered that the proper age for marriage in
any class depends on the duration of life in that class. Still, too early marriages are certainly not
unfrequent, and they are attended with other than economic evils, so that possibly even legal
measures might with advantage be resorted to for preventing them in all ranks by somewhat
postponing the age of full civil competence -- a change, however, which would not be without its
dangers. On the other hand, the Malthusians often speak too lightly of involuntary celibacy, not
recognising sufficiently that it is a deplorable necessity. They do not adequately estimate the value
of domestic life as a school of the civic virtues, and the social importance (even apart from personal
happiness) of the mutual affective education arising from the relations of the sexes in a well-
constituted union.
Malthus further infers from his principles that states should not artificially stimulate population, and
in particular that poor-laws should not be established, and, where they exist, should be abolished.
The first part of this proposition cannot be accepted as applying to every social phase, for it is
evident that in a case like that of ancient Rome, where continuous conquest was the chief
occupation of the national activity, or in other periods when protracted wars threatened the
independence or security of nations, statesmen might wisely take special action of the kind
deprecated by Malthus. In relation to modern industrial communities he is doubtless in general right,
though the promotion of immigration in new states is similar in principle to the encouragement of
population The question of poor-laws involves other considerations. The English system of his day
was, indeed, a vicious one, though acting in some degree as a corrective of other evils in our social
institutions; and efforts for its amendment tended to the public good. But the proposal of abolition is
one from which statesmen have recoiled, and which general opinion has never adopted. It is difficult
to believe that the present system will be permanent; it is too mechanical and undiscriminating; on
some sides too lax, it is often unduly rigorous in the treatment of the worthy poor who are the victims
of misfortune; and, in its ordinary modes of dealing with the young, it is open to grave objection. But
it would certainly be rash to abolish it; it is one of several institutions which will more wisely be
retained until the whole subject of the life of the working classes has been more thoroughly, and
also more sympathetically, studied. The position of Malthus with respect to the relief of destitution is
subject to this general criticism, that, first proving too much, he then shrinks from the consequences
of his own logic. it follows from his arguments, and is indeed explicitly stated in a celebrated
passage of his original essay, that he who has brought children into the world without adequate
provision for them should be left to the punishment of Nature, that "it is a miserable ambition to wish
to snatch the rod from her hand," and to defeat the action of her laws, which are the laws of God,
and which "have doomed him and his family to suffer." Though his theory leads him to this
conclusion, he could not, as a Christian clergyman, maintain the doctrine that, seeing our brother in
need, we ought to shut up our bowels of compassion from him; and thus he is involved in the radical
inconsequence of admitting the lawfulness, if not the duty, of relieving distress in cases where he
yet must regard the act as doing mischief to society. Buckle, who was imposed on by more than one
of the exaggerations of the economists, accepts the logical inference which Malthus evaded. He
alleges that the only ground on which we are justified in relieving destitution is the essentially self-
regarding one, that by remaining deaf to the appeal of the sufferer we should probably blunt the
edge of our own finer sensibilities.
It can scarcely be doubted that the favour which was at once accorded to the views of Malthus in
certain circles was due in part to an impression, very welcome to the higher ranks of society, that
they tended to relieve the rich and powerful of responsibility for the condition of the working classes,
by showing that the latter had chiefly themselves to blame, and not either the negligence of their
superiors or the institutions of the country. The application of his doctrines, too, made by some of his
successors had the effect of discouraging all active effort for social improvement. Thus Chalmers
"reviews seriatim, and gravely sets aside all the schemes usually proposed for the amelioration of
the economic condition of the people" on the ground that an increase of comfort will lead to an
increase of numbers, and so the last state of things will be worse than the first.
Malthus has in more recent times derived a certain degree of reflected lustre from the rise and wide
acceptance of the Darwinian hypothesis. Its author himself, in tracing its filiation, points to the
phrase "struggle ior existence" used by Malthus in relation to the social competition. Darwin believes
that man has advanced to his present relatively high condition through such a struggle, consequent
on his rapid multiplication. He regards, it is true, the agency of this cause for the improvement of our
race as largely superseded by moral influences in the more advanced social stages. Yet he
considers it, even in these stages, of so much importance towards that end, that notwithstanding the
individual suffering arising from the struggle for life, he deprecates any great reduction in the
natural, by which he seems to mean the ordinary, rate of increase.
There has been of late exhibited in some quarters a tendency to apply the doctrine of the "survival of
the fittest" to human society in such a way as to intensify the harsher features of Malthus's
exposition by encouraging the idea that whatever cannot sustain itself is fated, and must be allowed,
to disappear. But what is repellent in this conception is removed by a wide view of the influence of
humanity, as a disposing power, alike on vital and on social conditions. As in the general animal
domain the supremacy of man introduces a new force consciously controlling and ultimately
determining the destinies of the subordinate species, so human providence in the social sphere can
intervene for the protection of the weak, modifying by its deliberate action what would otherwise be
a mere contest of comparative strengths inspired by selfish instincts.(40)
David Ricardo (1772-1823) is essentially of the school of Smith, whose doctrines he in the main
accepts, whilst he seeks to develop them, and to correct them in certain particulars. But his mode of
treatment is very different from Smith's. The latter aims at keeping close to the realities of life as he
finds them, -- at representing the conditions and relations of men and things as they are; and, as
Hume remarked on first reading his great work, his principles are everywhere exemplified and
illustrated with curious facts. Quite unlike this is the way in which Ricardo proceeds. He moves in a
world of abstractions. He sets out from more or less arbitrary assumptions, reasons deductively from
these, and announces his conclusions as true, without allowing for the partial unreality of the
conditions assumed or confronting his results with experience. When he seeks to illustrate his
doctrines, it is from hypothetical cases, -- his favourite device being that of imagining two contracting
savages, and considering how they would be likely to act. He does not explain -- probably he had
not systematically examined, perhaps was not competent to examine -- the appropriate method of
political economy; and the theoretic defence of his mode of proceeding was left to be elaborated by
J. S. Mill and Cairnes. But his example had a great effect in determining the practice of his
successors. There was something highly attractive to the ambitious theorist in the sweeping march
of logic which seemed in Ricardo's hands to emulate the certainty and comprehensiveness of
mathematical proof, and in the portable and pregnant formulae which were so convenient in
argument, and gave a prompt, if often a more apparent than real, solution of difficult problems.
Whatever there was of false or narrow in the fundamental positions of Smith had been in a great
degree corrected by his practical sense and strong instinct for reality, but was br ought out in its full
dimensions and even exaggerated in the abstract theorems of Ricardo and his followers.
The dangers inherent in his method were aggravated by the extreme looseness of his phraseology .
Senior pronounces him "the most incorrect writer who ever attained philosophical eminence." His
most ardent admirers find him fluctuating and uncertain in the use of words, and generally trace his
errors to a confusion between the ordinary employment of a term and some special application of it
which he has himself devised.
The most complete exposition of his system is to be found in his Principles of Political Economy and
Taxation (1817). This work is not a complete treatise on the science, but a rather loosely connected
series of disquisitions on value and price, rent, wages, and profits, taxes, trade, money and banking.
Yet, though the connection of the parts is loose, the same fundamental ideas recur continually, and
determine the character of the entire scheme.
The principal problem to which he addresses himself in this work is that of distribution, -- that is to
say, the proportions of the whole produce of the country which will be allotted to the proprietor of
land, to the capitalist, and to the labourer.(41) And it is important to observe that it is especially the
variations in their respective portions which take place in the progress of society that he professes to
study, -- one of the most unhistorical of writers thus indicating a sense of the necessity of a doctrine
of economic dynamics -- a doctrine which, from his point of view, it was impossible to supply.
The principle which he puts first in order, and which is indeed the key to the whole, is this -- that the
exchange value of any commodity the supply of which can be increased at will is regulated, under a
régime of free competition, by the labour necessary for its production. Similar propositions are to be
found in the Wealth of Nations, not to speak of earlier English writings. Smith had said that, "in the
early and rude state of society which precedes both the accumulation of stock and the appropriation
of land, the proportion between the quantities of labour necessary for acquiring different objects
seems to be the only circumstance which can afford any rule ior exchanging them with one
another." But he wavers in his conception, and presents as the measure of value sometimes the
quantity of labour necessary for the production of the object, sometimes the quantity of labour which
the object would command in the market, which would be identical only for a given time and place.
The theorem requires correction for a developed social system by the introduction of the
consideration of capital, and takes the form in which it is elsewhere quoted from Malthus by Ricardo,
that the real price of a commodity "depends on the greater or less quantity of capital and labour
which must be employed to produce it." (The expression "quantity of capital" is lax, the element oi
time being omitted, but the meaning is obvious.) Ricardo, however, constantly takes no notice of
capital, mentioning labour alone in his statement of this principle, and seeks to justify his practice by
treating capital as "accumulated labour;" but this artificial way of viewing the facts obscures the
nature of the co-operation of capital in production, and by keeping the necessity of this co-operation
out of sight has encouraged some socialistic errors. Ricardo does not sufficiently distinguish
between the cause or determinant and the measure of value; nor does he carry back the principle of
cost of production as regulator of value to its foundation in the effect of that cost on the limitation of
supply. It is the "natural price" of a commodity that is fixed by the theorem we have stated; the
market price will be subject to accidental and temporary variations from this standard, depending on
changes in demand and supply; but the price will permanently and in the long run, depend on cost
of production defined as above. On this basis Ricardo goes on to explain the laws according to
which the produce of the land and the labour of the country is distributed amongst the several
classes which take part in production.
The theory of rent, with which he begins, though commonly associated with his name, and though it
certainly forms the most vital part of his general economic scheme, was not really his, nor did he lay
claim to it. He distinctly states in the preface to the Principles, that "in 1815 Mr. Malthus, in his
Inquiry into the Nature and Progress of Rent, and a fellow of University College, Oxford, in his Essay
on the Application of Capital to Land, presented to the world, nearly at the same moment, the true
doctrine of rent." The second writer here referred to was Sir Edward West, afterwards a judge of the
supreme court of Bombay. Still earlier than the time of Malthus and West, as M'Culloch has pointed
out, this doctrine had been clearly conceived and fully stated by Dr. James Anderson in his Enquiry
into the Nature of Corn-Laws, published at Edinburgh in 1777.(42) That this tract was unknown to
Malthus and West we have every reason to believe; but the theory is certainly as distinctly
enunciated and as satisfactorily supported in it as in their treatises; and the whole way in which it is
put forward by Anderson strikingly resembles the form in which it is presented by Ricardo.
The essence of the theory is that rent, being the price paid by the cultivator to the owner of land for
the use of its productive powers, is equal to the excess oi the price of the produce ot the land over
the cost of production on that land. With the increase of population, and therefore of demand for
food, inferior soils will be taken into cultivation; and the price of the entire supply necessary for the
community will be regulated by the cost of production of that portion of the supply which is produced
at the greatest expense. But for the land which will barely repay the cost of cultivation no rent will be
paid. Hence the rent of any quality of land will be equal to the difference between the cost of
production on that land and the cost of production of that produce which is raised at the greatest
expense.
The doctrine is perhaps most easily apprehended by means of the supposition here made of the
coexistence in a country of a series of soils of different degrees of fertility which are successively
taken into cultivation as population increases. But it would be an error to believe, though Ricardo
sometimes seems to imply it, that such difference is a necessary condition of the existence of rent. If
all the land of a country were of equal fertility, still if it were appropriated, and if the price oi the
produce were more than an equivalent for the labour and capital applied to its production, rent would
be paid. This imaginary case, however, after using it to clear our conceptions, we may ior the future
leave out of account.
The price of produce being, as we have said, regulated by the cost of production of that which pays
no rent, it is evident that "corn is not high because a rent is paid, but a rent is paid because corn is
high," and that "no reduction would take place in the price of corn although landlords should forego
the whole of their rent." Rent is, in fact, no determining element of price; it is paid, indeed, out oi the
price, but the price would be the same if no rent were paid, and the whole price were retained by the
cultivator.
It has often been doubted whether or not Adam Smith held this theory of rent. Sometimes he uses
language which seems to imply it, and states prepositions which, if developed, would infallibly lead
to it. Thus he says, in a passage already quoted, "Such parts only of the produce of land can
commonly be brought to market of which the ordinary price is sufficient to replace the stock which
must be employed in bringing them thither, together with its ordinary profits. If the ordinary price is
more than this, the surplus part of it will naturally go to the rent of land. If it is not more, though the
commodity can be brought to market, it can afford no rent to the landlord. Whether the price is or is
not more depends on the demand." Again, in Smith's application of these considerations to mines,
"the whole principle of rent," Ricardo tells us, "is admirably and perspicuously explained." But he
had formed the opinion that there is in fact no land which does not afford a rent to the landlord; and,
strangely, he seems to have seen that this appearance might arise from the aggregation into an
economic whole of parcels of land which can and others which cannot pay rent. The truth, indeed,
is, that the fact, if it were a fact, that all the land in a country pays rent would be irrelevant as an
argument against the Andersonian theory, for it is the same thing in substance if there be any capital
employed on land already cultivated which yields a return no more than equal to ordinary profits.
Such last-employed capital cannot afford rent at the existing rate of profit, unless the price of
produce should rise.
The belief which some have entertained that Smith, notwithstanding some vague or inaccurate
expressions, really held the Andersonian doctrine, can scarcely be maintained when we remember
that Hume, writing to him after having read for the first time the Wealth of Nations, whilst expressing
general agreement with his opinions, said (apparently with reference to Bk. I, chap. vii), "I cannot
think that the rent of farms makes any part of the price of the produce, but that the price is
determined altogether by the quantity and the demand." It is further noteworthy that a statement of
the theory of rent is even in the same volume, published in 1777, which contains Anderson's
polemic against Smith's objections to a bounty on the exportation of corn; this volume can hardly
have escaped Smith's notice, yet neither by its contents nor by Hume's letter was he led to modify
what he had said in his first edition on the subject of rent.
It must be remembered that not merely the unequal fertilities of different soils will determine
differences of rent; the more or less advantageous situation of a farm in relation to markets, and
therefore to roads and railways, will have a similar effect. Comparative lowness of the cost oi transit
will enable the produce to be brought to market at a smaller expense, and will thus increase the
surplus which constitutes rent. This consideration is indicated by Ricardo, though he does not give it
prominence, but dwells mainly on the comparative productiveness of soils.
Rent is defined by Ricardo as the price paid for the use of "the original and indestructible powers of
the soil." He thus differentiates rent, as he uses the term, from what is popularly designated by the
word; and, when it is to be taken in his sense, it is often qualified as the,"true" or "economic" rent.
Part of what is paid to the landlord is often really profit on his expenditure in preparing the farm for
cultivation by the tenant. But it is to be borne in mind that wherever such improvements are
"amalgamated with the land," and "add permanently to its productive powers," the return for them
follows the laws, not of profit, but of rent. Hence it becomes difficult, if not impossible, in practice to
discriminate with any degree of accuracy the amount received by the landlord "for the use of the
original powers of the soil" from the amount received by him as remuneration for his improvements
or those made by his predecessors. These have raised the farm, as an instrument for producing
food, from one class of productiveness to a higher, and the case is the same as if nature had
originally placed the land in question in that higher class.
Smith had treated it as the peculiar privilege of agriculture, as compared with other forms of
production, that in it "nature labours along with man," and therefore, whilst the workmen in
manufactures occasion the reproduction merely oi the capital which employs them with its owner's
profits, the agricultural labourer occasions the reproduction, not only of the employer's capital with
profits, but also of the rent of the landlord. This last he viewed as the free gift of nature which
remained "after deducting or compensating everything which can be regarded as the work of man."
Ricardo justly observes in reply that "there is not a manufacture which can be mentioned in which
nature doe not give her assistance to man." He then goes on to quote from Buchanan the remark
that "the notion of agriculture yielding a produce and a rent in consequence, because nature
concurs with industry in the process of cultivation, is a mere fancy. It is not from the produce, but
from the price at which the produce is sold, that the rent is derived; and this price is got, not because
nature assists in the production, but because it is the price which suits the consumption to the
supply."(43) There is no gain to the society at large from the rise of rent; it is advantageous to the
landlords alone, and their interests are thus permanently in opposition to those of all other classes.
The rise of rent may be retarded, or prevented, or even temporarily changed to a fall, by agricultural
improvements, such as the introduction of new manures or of machines or of a better organisation
of labour (though there is not so much room for this last as in other branches of production), or the
opening of new sources of supply in foreign countries ; but the tendency to a rise is constant so long
as the population increases.
The great importance of the theory of rent in Ricardo's system arises from the fact that he makes
the general economic condition of the society to depend altogether on the position in which
agricultural exploitation stands. This will be seen from the following statement of his theory of wages
and profits. The produce of every expenditure of labour and capital being divided between the
labourer and the capitalist, in proportion as one obtains more the other, will necessarily obtain less.
The productiveness of labour being given, nothing can diminish profit but a rise of wages or
increase it but a fall of wages. Now the price of labour, being the same as its cost of production, is
determined by the price of the commodities necessary for the support of the labourer. The price of
such manufactured articles as he requires has a constant tendency to fall, principally by reason of
the progressive application of the division of labour to their production. But the cost of his
maintenance essentially depends, not on the price of those articles, but on that of his food; and, as
the production of food will in the progress of society and of population require the sacrifice of more
and more labour, its price will rise; money wages will consequently rise, and with the rise of wages
profits will fall. Thus it is to the necessary gradual descent to inferior soils, or less productive
expenditure on the same soil, that the decrease in the rate of profit which has historically taken
place is to be attributed (Smith ascribed this decrease to the competition of capitalists, though in
one place, Book I, chap. ix,(44) he had a glimpse of the Ricardian view). This gravitation of profits
towards a minimum is happily checked at times by improvements of the machinery employed in the
production of necessaries, and especially by such discoveries in agriculture and other causes as
reduce the cost of the prime necessary of the labourer; but here again the tendency is constant.
Whilst the capitalist thus loses, the labourer does not gain ; his increased money wages only enable
him to pay the increased price of his necessaries, of which he will have no greater and probably a
less share than he had before. In fact, the labourer can never for any considerable time earn more
than what is required to enable the class to subsist in such a degree of comfort as custom has made
indispensable to them, and to perpetuate their race without either increase or diminution. That is the
"natural" price of labour; and if the market rate temporarily rises above it population will be
stimulated, and the rate of wages will again fall. Thus whilst rent has a constant tendency to rise and
profit to fall, the rise or fall of wages will depend on the rate of increase of the working classes. For
the improvement of their condition Ricardo thus has to fall back on the Malthusian remedy, of the
effective application of which he does not, however, seem to have much expectation. The securities
against a superabundant population to which he points are the gradual abolition of the poor-laws --
for their amendment would not content him -- and the development amongst the working classes of
a taste for greater comforts and enjoyments.
It will be seen that the socialists have somewhat exaggerated in announcing, as Ricardo's "iron law"
of wages, their absolute identity with the amount necessary to sustain the existence of the labourer
and enable him to continue the race. He recognizes the influence of a "standard of living" as limiting
the increase of the numbers of the working classes, and so keeping their wages above the lowest
point. But he also holds that, in long-settled countries, in the ordinary course of human affairs, and
in the absence of special efforts restricting the growth of population, the condition of the labourer will
decline as surely, and from the same causes, as that of the landlord will be improved.
If we are asked whether this doctrine of rent and the consequences which Ricardo deduced from it,
are true, we must answer that they are hypothetically true in the most advanced industrial
communities, and there only (though they have been rashly applied to the cases of India and
Ireland), but that even in those communities neither safe inference nor sound action can be built
upon them. As we shall see hereafter, the value of most of the theorems of the classical economics
is a good deal attenuated by the habitual assumptions that we are dealing with "economic men,"
actuated by one principle only; that custom, as against competition, has no existence; that there is
no such thing as combination; that there is equality of contract between the parties to each
transaction, and that there is a definite universal rate of profit and wages in a community; this last
postulate implying (1) that the capital embarked in any undertaking will pass at once to another in
which larger profits are for the time to be made; (2) that a labourer, whatever his local ties of feeling,
family, habit, or other engagements, will transfer himself immediately to any place where, or
employment in which, for the time, larger wages are to be earned than those he had previously
obtained;(45) and (3) that both capitalists and labourers have a perfect knowledge of the condition
and prospects of industry throughout the country, both in their own and other occupations. But in
Ricardo's speculations on rent and its consequences there is still more of abstraction. The influence
of emigration, which has assumed vast dimensions since his time, is left out of account, and the
amount of land at the disposal of a community is supposed limited to its own territory , whilst
contemporary Europe is in fact largely fed by the western States of America. We did not adequately
appreciate the degree in which the augmented productiveness of labour, whether from increased
intelligence, improved organization, introduction of machinery, or more rapid and cheaper
communication, steadily keeps down the cost of production. To these influences must be added
those of legal reforms in tenure, and fairer conditions in contracts, which operate in the same
direction. As a result of all these causes, the pressure anticipated by Ricardo is not felt, and the cry
is of the landlords over falling rents. not of the consumer over rising prices. The entire conditions are
in fact so altered that Professor Nicholson, no enemy to the "orthodox", economics, when recently
conducting an inquiry into the present state of the agricultural question,(46) pronounced the so-
called Ricardian theory of rent "too abstract to be of practical utility."
A particular economic subject on which Ricardo has thrown a useful light is the nature of the
advantages derived from foreign commerce, and the conditions under which such commerce can go
on. Whilst preceding writers had represented those benefits as consisting in affording a vent for
surplus produce, or enabling a portion of the national capital to replace itself with a profit, he pointed
out that they consist " simply and solely in this, that it enables each nation to obtain, with a given
amount of labour and capital, a greater quantity of all commodities taken together." This is no doubt
the point of view at which we should habitually place ourselves ; though the other forms of
expression employed by his predecessors, including Adam Smith, are sometimes useful as
representing real considerations affecting national production, and need not be absolutely disused.
Ricardo proceeds to show that what determines the purchase of any commodity from a foreign
country is not the circumstance that it can be produced there with less labour and capital than at
home. If we have a greater positive advantage in the production of some other article than in that of
the commodity in question, even though we have an advantage in producing the latter, it may be our
interest to devote ourselves to the production of that in which we have the greatest advantage, and
to import that in producing which we should have a less, though a real, advantage. It is, in short, not
absolute cost of production, but comparative cost, which determines the interchange. This remark is
just and interesting, though an undue importance seems to be attributed to it by J. S. Will and
Cairnes, the latter of whom magniloquently describes it as "sounding the depths" of the problem of
international dealings, -- though, as we shall see hereafter, he modifies it by the introduction of
certain considerations respecting the conditions of domestic production.
For the nation as a whole, according to Ricardo, it is not the gross produce of the land and labour,
as Smith seems to assert, that is of importance, but the net income -- the excess, that is, of this
produce over the cost of production, or, in other words, the amount of its rent and its profits; for the
wages of labour, not essentially exceeding the maintenance of the labourers, are by him considered
only as a part of the "necessary expenses of production." Hence it follows, as he himself in a
characteristic and often quoted passage says, that, "provided the net real income of the nation be
the same, it is of no importance whether it consists of ten or twelve millions of inhabitants. If five
millions of men could produce as much fond and clothing as was necessary for ten millions, food
and clothing for five millions would be the net revenue. Would it be of any advantage to the country
that to produce this same net revenue seven millions of men should be required, -- that is to say,
that seven millions should be employed to produce food and clothing sufficient for twelve millions?
The food and clothing of five millions would be still the net revenue. The employing a greater
number of men would enable us neither to add a man to our army and navy nor to contribute one
guinea more in taxes." Industry is here viewed, just as by the mercantilists, in relation to the military
and political power of the state, not to the maintenance and improvement of human beings, as its
end and aim. The labourer, as Held(47) has remarked, is regarded not as a member of society, but
as a means to the ends of society, on whose sustenance a part of the gross income must be
expended, as another part must be spent on the sustenance of horses. We may well ask, as
Sismondi did in a personal interview with Ricardo, "What! is wealth then everything? are men
absolutely nothing!"
On the whole what seems to us true of Ricardo is this, that, whilst he had remarkable powers, they
were not the powers best fitted for sociological research. Nature intended him rather for a
mathematician of the second order than for a social philosopher. Nor had he the due previous
preparation for social studies; for we must decline to accept Bagehot's idea that, though " in no high
sense an educated man," he had a specially apt trailing for such studies in his practice as an
eminently successful dealer in stocks. The same writer justly notices the "anxious penetration with
which he follows out rarefied minutia." But he wanted breadth of survey, a comprehensive view of
human nature and human life, and the strong social sympathies which, as the greatest minds have
recognized, are a most valuable aid in this department of study. On a subject like that of money,
where a few elementary propositions-into which no moral ingredient enters-have alone to be kept in
view, he was well adapted to succeed; but in the larger social field he is at fault. He had great
deductive readiness and skill (though his logical accuracy, as Mr. Sidgwick remarks, has been a
good deal exaggerated). But in human affairs phenomena are so complex, and principles so
constantly limit or even compensate one another, that rapidity and daring in deduction may be the
greatest of dangers, if they are divorced from a wide and balanced appreciation of facts. Dialectic
ability is, no doubt, a valuable gift, but the first condition for success in social investigation is to see
things as they are.
A sort of Ricardo-mythus for some time existed in economic circles. It cannot be doubted that the
exaggerated estimate of his merits arose in part from a sense of the support his system gave to the
manufacturers and other capitalists in their growing antagonism to the old aristocracy of
landowners. The same tendency, as well as his affinity to their too abstract and unhistorical modes
of thought, and their eudamonistic doctrines, recommended him to the Benthamite group, and to the
so-called Philosophical Radicals generally. Brougham said he seemed to have dropped from the
skies-a singular avatar, it must be owned. His real services in connection with questions of currency
and banking naturally created a prepossession in favour of his more general views, But, apart from
those special subjects, it does not appear that, either in the form of solid theoretic teaching or of
valuable practical guidance, he has really done much for the world, whilst he admittedly misled
opinion on several important questions. De Quincey's presentation of him as a great revealer of
truth is now seen to be an extravagance. J. S. Mill and others speak of his "superior lights " as
compared with those of Adam Smith; but his work, as a contribution to our knowledge of human
society, will not bear a moment's comparison with the Wealth of Nations.
It is interesting to observe that Malthus, though the combination of his doctrine of population with the
principles of Ricardo composed the creed for some time professed by all the "orthodox "
economists, did not himself accept the Ricardian scheme. He prophesied that " the main part of the
structure would not stand." "The theory," he says", takes a partial view of the subject, like the system
of the French economists; and, like that system, after having drawn into its vortex a great number of
very clever men, it will be unable to support itself against the testimony of obvious facts, and the
weight of those theories which, though less simple and captivating, are more just on account of their
embracing more of the causes which are in actual operation in all economical results." We saw that
the foundations of Smith's doctrine in general philosophy were unsound, and the ethical character of
his scheme in consequence injuriously affected; but his mode of treatment, consisting in the
habitual combination of induction and deduction, we found little open to objection. Mainly through
the influence of Ricardo, economic method was perverted. The science was led into the mistaken
course of turning its back on observation, and seeking to evolve the laws of phenomena out of a few
hasty generalisations by a play of logic. The principal vices which have been in recent times not
unjustly attributed to the members of the "orthodox " school were all encouraged by his example,
namely,-(1) the viciously abstract character of the conceptions with which they deal, (2) the abusive
preponderance of deduction in their processes of research, and (3) the too absolute way in which
their conclusions are conceived and enunciated.
The works of Ricardo have been collected in one volume, with a biographical notice, by J. R.
M'Culloch (1846).(48)
After Malthus and Ricardo, the first of whom had fixed pubiic attention irresistibly on certain aspects
of society, and the second had led economic research into new, if questionable, paths, came a
number of minor writers who were mainly their expositors and commentators, and whom,
accordingly, the Germans, with allusion to Greek mythical history, designate as the Epigoni. By
them the doctrines of Smith and his earliest successors were thrown into more systematic shape,
limited and guarded so as to be less open to criticism, couched in a more accurate terminology,
modified in subordinate particulars, or applied to the solution of the practical questions of their day.
James Mill's Elements (1821) deserves special notice, as exhibiting the system of Ricardo with
thoroughgoing rigour, and with a compactness of presentation, and a skill in the disposition of
materials, which give to it in some degree the character of a work of art. The a priori political
economy is here reduced to its simplest expression. J. R. M'Culloch - (1779-1864), author of a
number of laborious statistical and other compilations, criticised current economic legislation in the
Edinburgh Review from the point of view of the Ricardian doctrine, taking up substantially the same
theoretic position as was occupied at a somewhat later period by the Manchester school. He is
altogether without originality, and never exhibits any philosophic elevation or breadth. His confident
dogmatism is often repellent; he admitted in his later years that he had been too fond of novel
opinions, and defended them with more heat and pertinacity than they deserved. It is noticeable
that, though often spoken of in his own time both by those who agreed with his views, and those,
like Sismondi, who differed from them, as one of the lights of the reigning school, his name is now
tacitly dropped in the writings of the members of that school. Whatever may have been his partial
usefulness in vindicating the policy of free trade, it is at least plain that for the needs of our social
future he has nothing to offer. Nassau William Senior (1790-1864), who was professor of political
economy in the university of Oxford, published, besides a number of separate lectures, a treatise on
the science, which first appeared as an article in the
Enclyopaedia Metropolitana. He is a writer of a high order of merit. He made considerable
contributions to the elucidation of economic principles, specially studying exactness in nomenclature
and strict accuracy in deduction. His explanations on cost of production and the way in which it
affects price, on rent, on the difference between rate of wages and price of labour, on the relation
between profit and wages (with special reference to Ricardo's theorem on this subject, which he
corrects by the substitution of proportional for absolute amount), and on the distribution of the
precious metals between different countries, are particularly valuable. His new term "abstinence,"
invented to express the conduct for which interest is the remuneration, was useful, though not quite
appropriate, because negative in meaning. It is on the theory of wages that Senior is least
satisfactory. He makes the average rate in a country (which, we must maintain, is not a real quantity,
though the rate in a given employment and neighbourhood is) to be expressed by the fraction of
which the numerator is the amount of the wages fund (an unascertainable and indeed, except as
actual total of wages paid, imaginary sum) and the denominator the number of the working
population; and from this he proceeds to draw the most important and far-reaching consequences,
though the equation on which he founds his inferences conveys at most only an arithmetical fact,
which would be true of every case of a division amongst individuals, and contains no economic
element whatever. The phrase "wages fund" originated in some expressions of Adam Smith(49)
used only for the purpose of illustration, and never intended to be rigorously interpreted; and we
shall see that the doctrine has been repudiated by several members of what is regarded as the
orthodox school of political economy. As regards method, Senior makes the science a purely
deductive one, in which there is no room for any other "facts " than the four fundamental
propositions from which he undertakes to deduce all economic truth. And he does not regard
himself as arriving at hypothetic conclusions; his postulates and his inferences are alike conceived
as corresponding to actual phenomena.(50) Colonel Robert Torrens (1780-1864) was a prolific
writer, partly on economic theory, but principally on its applications to financial and commercial
policy. Almost the whole of the programme which was carried out in legislation by Sir Robert Peel
had been laid down in principle in the writings of Torrens. He gave substantially the same theory of
foreign trade which was afterwards stated by J. S. Mill in one of his Essays on Unsettled Questions.
(51) He was an early and earnest advocate of the repeal of the corn laws, but was not in favour of a
general system of absolute free trade, maintaining that it is expedient to impose retaliatory duties to
countervail similar duties imposed by foreign countries, and that a lowering of import duties on the
productions of countries retaining their hostile tariffs would occasion an abstraction of the precious
metals, and a decline in prices, profits, and wages.
His principal writings of a general character were- The Economist [i.e., Physiocrat] Refuted, 1808;
Essay on the Production of Wealth, 1821; Essay on the External Corn Trade (eulogised by Ricardo),
3d ed., 1826; The Budget, a series of Letters on Financial, Commercial, and Colonial Policy, 1841-
3. Harriet Martineau (1802-1876) popularised the doctrines of Malthus and Ricardo in her
Illustrations of Political Economy (1832-34), a series of tales, in which there is much excellent
description, but the effect of the narrative is often marred by the somewhat ponderous disquisitions
here and there thrown in, usually in the form of dialogue.
Other writers who ought to be named in any history of the science are Charles Babbage, On the
Economy of Machinery and Manufactures (1832), chiefly descriptive, but also in part theoretic;
William Thomas Thornton, Overpopulation and its Remedy (1846), A Plea for Peasant Proprietors
(1848), On Labour (1869; 2d ed., 1870); Herman Merivale, Lectures on Colonisation and Colonies
(1841-2; new ed., 1861); T. C. Banfield, The Organisation of Industry Explained (1844; 2d ed.,
1848); and Edward Gibbon Wakefield, A View of the Art of Colonisation (1849). Thomas Chalmers,
well known in other fields of thought, was author of The Christian and civic Economy of Large
Towns (1821-36), and On Political Economy in Connection with the Moral State and Moral
Propsects of Society (1832); he strongly opposed any system of legal charity, and whilst justly
insisting on the primary importance of morality, industry, and thrift as conditions of popular well-
being, carried the Malthusian doctrines to excess. Nor was Ireland without a share in the economic
movement of the period.(52) Whately, having been second Drummond professor of political
economy at Oxford (in succession to Senior), and delivered in that capacity his Introductory
Lectures (1831), founded in 1832, when he went to Ireland as archbishop of Dublin, a similar
professorship in Trinity College, Dublin. It was first held by Mountifort Longfield, afterwards Judge of
the Landed Estates Court, Ireland (d. 1884). He published lectures on the science generally (1834),
on Poor Laws (1834), and on Commerce and Absenteeism (1835), which were marked by
independence of thought and sagacious observation. He was laudably free from many of the
exaggerations of his contemporaries; he said, in 1835, "in political economy we must not abstract
too much," and protested against the assumption commonly made that " men are guided in all their
conduct by a prudent regard to their own interest." James A. Lawson (afterwards Mr. Justice
Lawson, d. 1887) also published some lectures (1844), delivered from the same chair, which may
still be read with interest and profit; his discussion of the question of population is especially good;
he also asserted against Senior that the science is avide de faits, and that it must reason about the
world and mankind as they really are.
The most systematic and thoroughgoing of the earlier critics of the Ricardian system was Richard
Jones (1790-1855), professor at Haileybury. Jones has received scant justice at the hands of his
successors. J. S. Mill, whilst using his work, gave his merits but faint recognition. Even Roscher
says that he did not thoroughly understand Ricardo, without giving any proof of that assertion, whilst
he is silent as to the fact that much of what has been preached by the German historical school is
found distinctly indicated in Jones's writings. He has been sometimes represented as having
rejected the Andersonian doctrine of rent; but such a statement is incorrect. Attributing the doctrine
to Malthus, he says that that economist " showed satisfactorily that when land is cultivated by
capitalists living on the profits of their stock, and able to move it at pleasure to other employments,
the expense of tilling the worst quality of land cultivated determines the average price of raw
produce, while the difference of quality of the superior lands measures the rents yielded by them. "
What he really denied was the application of the doctrine to all cases where rent is paid; he pointed
out in his Essay on the Distribution of Wealth and on the Sources of Taxation, 1831, that besides
"farmers' rents," which, under the supposed conditions, conform to the above law, there are
"peasant rents," paid everywhere through the most extended periods of history, and still paid over by
far the largest part of the earth's surface, which are not so regulated. Peasant rents he divided under
the heads of (1) serf, (2) mitayer, (3) ryot, and (4) cottier rents, a classification afterwards adopted in
substance by J. S. Mill; and he showed that the contracts fixing their amount were, at least in the
first three classes, determined rather by custom than by competition. Passing to the superstructure
of theory erected by Ricardo on the doctrine of rent which he had so unduly extended, Jones denied
most of the conclusions he had deduced, especially the following: --that the increase of farmers'
rents is always contemporary with a decrease in the productive powers of agriculture, and comes
with loss and distress in its train; that the interests of landlords are always and necessarily opposed
to the interests of the state and of every other class of society,. that the diminution of the rate of
profits is - exclusively dependent on the returns to the capital last employed on the land; and that
wages can rise only at the expense of profits.
The method followed by Jones is inductive; his conclusions are founded on a wide observation of
contemporary facts, aided by the study of history. " If," he said, "we wish to make ourselves
acquainted with the economy and arrangements by which the different nations of the earth produce
and distribute their revenues, I really know of but one way to attain our object, and that is, to look
and see. We must get comprehensive views of facts, that we may arrive at principles that are truly
comprehensive. If we take a different method, if we snatch at general principles, and content
ourselves with confined observations, two things will happen to us. First, what we call general
principles will often be found to have no generality--we shall set out with declaring propositions to be
universally true which, at every step of our further progress, we sh&ll be obliged to confess are
frequently false; and, secondly, we shall miss a great mass of useful knowledge which those who
advance to principles by a comprehensive examination of facts necessarily meet with on their road."
The world he professed to study was not an imaginary world, inhabited by abstract "economic men,"
but the real world with the different forms which the ownership and cultivation of land, and, in
general, the conditions of production and distribution, assume at different times and places. His
recognition of such different systems of life in communities occupying different stages in the
progress of civilisation led to his proposal of what he called a "political economy of nations." This
was a protest against the practice of taking the exceptional state of facts which exists, and is indeed
only partially realised, in a small corner of our planet as representing the uniform type of human
societies, and ignoring the effects of the early history and special development of each community
as influencing its economic phenomena.
It is sometimes attempted to elude the necessity for a wider range of study by alleging a universal
tendency in the social world to assume this now exceptional shape as its normal and ultimate
constitution. Even if this tendency were real (which is only partially true, for the existing order
amongst ourselves cannot be regarded % entirely definitive), it could not be admitted that the facts
witnessed in our civilization and those exhibited in less advanced communities are so approximate
as to be capable of being represented by the same formula. As Whewell, in editing Jones's
Remains, 1859, well observed, it is true in the physical world that " all things tend to assume a form
determined by the force of gravity; the hills tend to become plains, the water, the rivers to falls to eat
away their beds and disappear, form lakes in the valleys, the glaciers to pour down in cataracts." But
are we to treat these results as achieved, because forces are in operation which may ultimately
bring them about? All human questions are largely questions of time i and the economic
phenomena which really belong to the several stages of the human movement must be studied as
they are, unless we are content to fall into grievous error both in our theoretic treatment of them and
in the solution of the practical problems they present.
Jones is remarkable for his freedom from exaggeration and one-sided statement; thus, whilst
holding Malthus in, perhaps, undue esteem, he declines to accept the proposition that an increase
of the means of subsistence is necessarily followed by an increase of population; and he maintains
what is undoubtedly true, that with the growth of population, in all well-governed and prosperous
states, the command over food, instead of diminishing, increases.
Much of what he has left us-a large part of which is unfortunately fragmentary-is akin to the labours
of Cliffe Leslie at a later period. The latter, however, had the advantage of acquaintance with the
sociology of Comte, which gave him a firmer grasp of method, as well as a wider view of the general
movement of society; and, whilst the voice of Jones was but little heard amidst the general applause
accorded to Ricardo in the economic world of his time, Leslie wrote when disillusion had set in, and
the current was beginning to turn in England against the a priori economics.
Comte somewhere speaks of the "transient predilection " for political economy which had shown
itself generally in western Europe. This phase of feeling was specially noticeable in England from
the third to the fifth decade of the present century. " Up to the year 1818," said a writer in the
Westminister Review", the science was scarcely known or talked of beyond a small circle of
philosophers; and legislation, so far from being in conformity with its principles, was daily receding
from them more and more. "Mill has told us what a change took place within a few years. "Political
economy ", he says", had asserted itself with great vigour in public affairs by the petition of the
merchants of London for free trade, drawn up in 1820 by Mr. Tooke and presented by Mr. Alexander
Baring,(53) and by the noble exertions of Ricardo during the few years of his parliamentary life. His
writings, following up the impulse given by the bullion controversy, and followed up in their turn by
the expositions and comments of my father and M'Culloch (whose writings in the Edinburgh Review
during those years were most valuable), had drawn general attention to the subject, making at least
partial converts in the Cabinet itself. and Huskisson, supported by Canning, had commenced that
gradual demolition of the protective system which one of their colleagues " [Peel] "virtually
completed in 1846, though the last vestiges were only swept away by Mr. Gladstone in 1860." Whilst
the science was thus attracting and fixing the attention of active minds, its unsettled condition was
freely admitted. The differences of opinion among its professors were a frequent subject of
complaint. But it was confidently expected that these discrepancies would soon disappear, and
Colonel Torrens predicted that in twenty years there would scarcely "exist a doubt respecting any of
its more fundamental principles." "The prosperity, " says Mr. Sidgwick, " that followed on the
abolition of the corn laws gave practical men a most impressive and satisfying proof of the
soundness of the abstract reasoning by which the expediency of free trade had been inferred," and
when, in 1848, "a masterly expositor of thought had published a skilful statement of the chief results
of the controversies of the preceding generation," with the due " explanations and qualifications " of
the reigning opinions, it was for some years generally believed that political economy had " emerged
from the state of polemical discussion," at least on its leading doctrines, and that at length a sound
construction had been erected on permanent bases.
This expositor was John Stuart Mill (1806-73). He exercised, without doubt, a greater influence in
the field of English economics than any other writer since Ricardo. His systematic treatise has been,
either directly or through manuals founded on it, especially that of Fawcett, the source from which
most of our contemporaries in these countries have derived their knowledge of the science. But
there are other and deeper reasons, as we shall see, which make him, in this as in other
departments of knowledge, a specially interesting and significant figure.
In 1844 he published five Essays on some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy, which had
been written as early as 1829 and 1830, but had, with the exception of the fifth, remained in
manuscript. In these essays is contained any dogmatic contribution which he can be regarded as
having made to the science. The subject of the first is the laws of interchange between nations. He
shows that, when two countries trade together in two commodities, the prices of the commodities
exchanged on both sides (which, as Ricardo had proved, are not determined by cost of production)
will adjust themselves, through the play of reciprocal demand, in such a way that the quantities
required by each country of the article which it imports from its neighbour shall be exactly sufficient
to pay for one another. This is the law which appears, with some added developments, in his
systematic treatise under the name of the "equation of international demand." He then discusses the
division of the gains. The most important practical conclusion (not, however, by any means an
undisputed one) at which he arrives in this essay is, that the relaxation of duties on foreign
commodities, not operating as protection but maintained solely for revenue should be made
contingent on the adoption of some corresponding degree of freedom of trade with England by the
nation from which the commodities are imported. In the second essay, on the influence of
consumption on production, the most interesting results arrived at are the propositions-(1) that
absenteeism is a local, not a national, evil, and (2) that, whilst there cannot be permanent excess of
production, there may be a temporary excess, not only of any one article, but of commodities
generally,-this last, however, not arising from over-production, but from a want of commercial
confidence. The third essay relates to the use of the words "productive" and "unproductive" as
applied to labour, to consumption, and to expenditure. The fourth deals with profits and interest,
especially explaining and so justifying Ricardo's theorem that "profits depend on wages, rising as
wages fall and falling as wages rise." What Ricardo meant was that profits depend on the cost of
wages estimated in labour. Hence improvements in the production of articles habitually consumed
by the labourer may increase profits without diminishing the real remuneration of the labourer. The
last essay is on the definition and method of political economy, a subject later and more maturely
treated in the author's System of Logic.
In 1848 Mill published his Principles of Political Economy, with some of their Applications to Social
Philosophy. This title, though, as we shall see, open to criticism, indicated on the part of the author a
less narrow and formal conception of the field of the science than had been common amongst his
predecessors. He aimed, in fact, at producing a work which might replace in ordinary use the
Wealth of Nations, which in his opinion was "in many parts obsolete and in all imperfect." Adam
Smith had invariably associated the general principles of the subject with their applications, and in
treating those applications had often appealed to other and far larger considerations than pure
political economy affords, And in the same spirit Mill desired, whilst incorporating all the results
arrived at in the special science by Smith's successors, to exhibit purely economic phenomena in
relation to the most advanced conceptions of his own time on the general philosophy of society, as
Smith had done in reference to the philosophy of the eighteenth century.(54)
This design he certainly failed to realise. His book is very far indeed from being a "modern Adam
Smith." It is an admirably lucid and even elegant exposition of the Ricardian economics, the
Malthusian theory being of course incorporated with these, but, notwithstanding the introduction of
many minor novelties, it is, in its scientific substance, little or nothing more. When Cliffe Leslie says
that Mill so qualified and amended the doctrines of Ricardo that the latter could scarcely have
recognized them, he certainly goes a great deal too far,. Senior really did more in that direction.
Mill's effort is usually to vindicate his master where others have censured him, and to palliate his
admitted laxities of expression. Already his profound esteem for Ricardo' s services to economics
had been manifest in his Essays, where he says of him, with some injustice to Smith, that, "having a
science to create," he could not "occupy himself with more than the leading principles,.' and adds
that "no one who has thoroughly entered into his discoveries " will find any difficulty in working out "
even the minutiae of the science." James Mill, too, had been essentially an expounder of Ricardo;
and the son, whilst greatly superior to his father in the attractiveness of his expository style, is, in
regard to his economic doctrine, substantially at the same point of view. It is in their general
philosophical conceptions and their views of social aims and ideals that the elder and younger Mill
occupy quite different positions in the line of progress. The latter could not, for example, in his adult
period have put forward as a theory of government the shallow sophistries which the plain good
sense of Macaulay sufficed to expose in the writings of the former; and he had a nobleness of
feeling which, in relation to the higher social questions, raised him far above the ordinary coarse
utilitarianism of the Benthamites.
The larger and more philosophic spirit in which Mill dealt with social subjects was undoubtedly in
great measure due to the influence of Comte, to whom, as Bain justly says, he was under greater
obligations than he himself was disposed to admit. Had he more completely undergone that
influence we are sometimes tempted to think he might have wrought the reform in economics which
still remains to be achieved, emancipating the science from the a priori; system, and founding a
genuine theory of industrial life on observation in the broadest sense. But probably the time was not
ripe for such a construction, and it is possible that Mill's native intellectual defects might have made
him unfit for the task, for, as Roscher has said, "ein historischer Kopf war er nicht." However this
might have been, the effects of his early training, in which positive were largely alloyed with
metaphysical elements, sufficed in fact to prevent his attaining a perfectly normal mental attitude.
He never altogether overcame the vicious direction which he had received from the teaching of his
father, and the influence of the Benthamite group in which he was brought up. Hence it was that,
according to the striking expression of Roscher, his whole view of life was "zu wenig aus Einem
Gusse. " The incongruous mixture of the narrow dogmas of his youthful period with the larger ideas
of a later stage gave a wavering and undeterminate character to his entire philosophy. He is, on
every side, eminently " un-final; " he represents tendencies to new forms of opinion, and opens new
vistas in various directions, but founds scarcely anything, and remains indeed, so far as his own
position is concerned, not merely incomplete but incoherent.(55) It is, however, precisely this
dubious position which seems to us to give a special interest to his career, by fitting him in a
peculiar degree to prepare and facilitate transitions.
What he himself thought to be "the chief merit of his treatise " was the marked distinction drawn
between the theory of production and that of distribution, the laws of the former being based on
unalterable natural facts, whilst the course of distribution is modified from time to time by the
changing ordinances of society. This distinction, we may remark, must not be too absolutely stated,
for the organization of production changes with social growth, and, as Lauderdale long ago showed,
the nature of the distribution in a community reacts on production. But there is a substantial truth in
the distinction, and the recognition of it tends to concentrate attention on the question-How can we
improve the existing distribution of wealth? The study of this problem led Mill, as he advanced in
years, further and further in the direction of socialism; and, whilst to the end of his life his book,
however otherwise altered, continued to deduce the Ricardian doctrines from the principle of
enlightened selfishness, he was looking forward to an order of things in which synergy should be
founded on sympathy.
The gradual modification of his views in relation to the economic constitution of society is set forth in
his Autobiography. In his earlier days, he tells us, he "had seen little further than the old school"
(note this significant title) "of political economy into the possibilities of fundamental improvement in
social arrangements. Private property, as now understood, and inheritance appeared the dernier
mot of legislation." The notion of proceeding to any radical redress of the injustice " involved in the
fact that some are born to riches and the vast majority to poverty " he had then reckoned chimerical.
But now his views were such as would " class him decidedly under the general designation of
socialist; " he had been led to believe that the whole contemporary framework of economic life was
merely temporary and provisional, and that a time would come when " the division of the produce of
labour, instead of depending, as in so great a degree it now does, on the accident of birth, would be
made by concert on an acknowledged principle of justice." "The social problem of the future " he
considered to be "how to unite the greatest individual liberty of action," which was often
compromised in socialistic schemes, " with a common ownership in the raw material of the globe,
and an equal participation in all the benefits of combined labour. " These ideas, he says, were
scarcely indicated in the first edition of the Political Economy, rather more clearly and fully in the
second, and quite unequivocally in the third, the French Revolution of 1848 having made the public
more open to the reception of novelties in opinion.
Whilst thus looking forward to a new economic order, he yet thinks its advent very remote, and
believes that the inducements of private interest will in the meantime be indispensable.(56) On the
spiritual side he maintains a similar attitude of expectancy. He anticipates the ultimate
disappearance of theism, and the substitution of a purely human religion, but believes that the
existing doctrine will long be necessary as a stimulus and a control. He thus saps existing
foundations without providing anything to take their place, and maintains the necessity of conserving
for indefinite periods what he has radically discredited. Nay, even whilst sowing the seeds of change
in the direction of a socialistic organisation of society, he favours present or proximate
arrangements which would urge the industrial, world towards other issues. The system of peasant
proprietorship of land is distinctly individualistic in its whole tendency,. yet he extravagantly praises it
in the earlier part of his book, only receding from that laudation when he comes to the chapter on
the future of the labouring classes. And the system of so-called co-operation in production which he
so warmly commended in the later editions of his work, and led some of his followers to preach as
the one thing needful, would inevitably strengthen the principle of personal property, and, whilst
professing at most to substitute the competition of associations for that of individuals, would by no
means exclude the latter.
The elevation of the working classes he bound up too exclusively with the Malthusian ethics, on
which he laid quite an extravagant stress, though, as Bain has observed, it is not easy to make out
his exact views, any more than his father's, on this subject. We have no reason to think that he ever
changed his opinion as to the necessity of a restriction on population; yet that element seems
foreign to the socialistic idea to which he increasingly leaned. It ij at least difficult to see how, apart
from individual responsibility for the support of a family, what Malthus called moral restraint could be
adequately enforced. This difficulty is indeed the fatal flaw which, in Malthus's own opinion, vitiated
the scheme of Godwin.
Mill's openness to new ideas and his enthusiasm for improvement cannot be too much admired. But
there appears to have been combined with these fine traits in his mental constitution a certain want
of practical sense, a failure to recognize and acquiesce in the necessary conditions of human life,
and a craving for "better bread than can be made of wheat." He entertained strangely exaggerated,
or rather perverted, notions of the "subjection", the capacities, and the rights of women. He
encourages a spirit of revolt on the part of working men against their perpetual condemnation, as a
class, to the lot of living by wages, without having satisfactory proof that this state of things is
capable of change, and without showing that such a lot, duly regulated by law and morality, is
inconsistent with their real happiness. He also insists on the "independence" of the working class --
which, according to him, farà da sè--in such a way as to obscure, if not to controvert, the truths that
superior rank and wealth are naturally invested with social power, and are bound in duty to exercise
it for the benefit of the community it large, and especially of its less favoured members, And he
attaches a quite undue importance to mechanical and indeed, illusory expedients, such as the
limitation of the power of bequest and the confiscation of the "unearned increment " of rent.
With respect to economic method also, he shifted his position; yet to the end occupied uncertain
ground. In the fifth of his early essays he asserted that the method a priori; is the only mode of
investigation in the social sciences, and that the method a posteriori; " is altogether inefficacious in
those sciences, as a means of arriving at any considerable body of valuable truth." When he wrote
his Logic, he had learned from Comte that the a posteriori method-in the form which he chose to call
"inverse deduction"--was the only mode of arriving at truth in general sociology; and his admission
of this at once renders the essay obsolete. But, unwilling to relinquish the a priori method of his
youth, he tries to establish a distinction of two sorts of economic inquiry, one of which, though not
the other, can be handled by that method. Sometimes he speaks of political economy as a
department "carved out of the general body of the science of society,." whilst on the other hand the
title of his systematic work implies a doubt whether political economy is a part of "social philosophy "
at all, and not rather a study preparatory and auxiliary to it. Thus, on the logical as well as the
dogmatic side, he halts between two opinions. Notwithstanding his misgivings and even disclaimers,
he yet remained, as to method, a member of the old school, and never passed into the new or
"historical " school, to which the future belongs. The question of economic method was also taken
up by the ablest of his disciples, John Elliott Cairnes (1824-75), who devoted a volume to the
subject (Logical Method of Political Economy, 1857,. 2d ed., 1875). Professor Walker has spoken of
the method advocated by Cairnes as being different from that put forward by Mill, and has even
represented the former as similar to, if not identical with, that of the German historical school. But
this is certainly an error. Cairnes, notwithstanding some apparent vacillation of view and certain
concessions more formal than real, maintains the utmost rigour of the deductive method; he
distinctly affirms that in political economy there is no room for induction at all, "the economist
starting with a knowledge of ultimate causes," and being thus, " at the outset of his enterprise, at the
position which the physicist only attains after ages of laborious research." He does not, indeed,
seem to be advanced beyond the point of view of Senior, who professed to deduce all economic
truth from four elementary propositions. Whilst Mill in his Logic represents verification as an
essential part of the proccss of demonstration of economic laws, Cairnes holds that, as they "are not
assertions respecting the character or sequence of phenomena " (though what else can a scientific
law be ?), "they can neither be established nor refuted by statistical or documentary evidence." A
proposition which affirms nothing respecting phenomena cannot be controlled by being confronted
with phenomena. Notwithstanding the unquestionable ability of his book, it appears to mark, in some
respects, a retrogression in methodology, and can for the future possess only an historical interest.
Regarded in that light, the labours of Mill and Cairnes on the method of the science, though
intrinsically unsound, had an important negative effect. They let down the old political economy from
its traditional position, and reduced its extravagant pretensions by two modifications of commonly
accepted views. First, whilst Ricardo had never doubted that in all his reasonings he was dealing
with human beings as they actually exist, they showed that the science, as he conceived it, must be
regarded as a purely hypothetic one, Its deductions are based on unreal, or at least one-sided,
assumptions, the most essential of which is that of the existence of the so-called "economic man", a
being who is influenced by two motives only, that of acquiring wealth and that of avoiding exertion;
and only so far as the premises framed on this conception correspond with fact can the conclusions
be depended on in practice. Senior in vain protested against such a view of the science, which, as
he saw, compromised its social efficacy,. whilst Torrens, who had previously combated the doctrines
of Ricardo, hailed Mill's new presentation of political economy as enabling him, whilst in one sense
rejecting those doctrines, in another sense to accept them. Secondly, beside economic science, it
had often been said, stands an economic art,--the former ascertaining truths. respecting the laws of
economic phenomena, the latter prescribing the right kind of economic action; and many had
assumed that, the former being given, the latter is also in our possession-that, in fact, we have only
to convert theorems into precepts, and the work is done. But Mill and Cairnes made it plain that this
statement could not be accepted, that action can no more in the economic world than in any other
province of life be regulated by considerations borrowed from one department of things only; that
economics can suggest ideas which are to be kept in view, but that, standing alone, it cannot direct
conduct--an office for which a wider prospect of human affairs is required. This matter is best
elucidated by a reference to Comte's classification, or rather hierarchical arrangement, of the
sciences. Beginning with the least complex, mathematics, we rise successively to astronomy,
physics, chemistry, thence to biology, and from it again to sociology. In the course of this ascent we
come upon all the great laws which regulate the phenomena of the inorganic world, of organised
beings, and of society. A further step, however, remains to be taken-namely, to morals,. and at this
point the provinces of theory and practice tend to coincide, because every element of conduct has to
be considered in relation to the general good. In the final synthesis all the previous analyses have to
be used as instrumental, in order to determine how every real quality of things or men may be made
to converge to the welfare of Humanity.
Cairnes's most important economic publication was his last, entitled Some Leading Principles of
Political Economy newly Expounded, 1874. In this work, which does not profess to be a complete
treatise on the science, he criticises and emends the statements which preceding writers had given
of some of its principal doctrines, and treats elaborately of the limitations with which they are to be
understood, and the exceptions to them which may be produced by special circumstances. Whilst
marked by great ability, it affords evidence of what has been justly observed as a weakness in
Cairnes's mental constitution--his "deficiency in intellectual sympathy, " and consequent frequent
inability to see more than one side of a truth.
The three divisions of the book relate respectively to (1) value, (2) labour and capital, and (3)
international trade, In the first he begins by elucidating the meaning of the word "value," and under
this head controverts the view of Jevons that the exchange value of anything depends entirely on its
utility, without, perhaps, distinctly apprehending what Jevons meant by this proposition. On supply
and demand he shows, as Say had done before, that these, regarded as aggregates, are not
independent, but strictly connected and mutually dependent phenomena-identical, indeed, under a
system of barter, but under a money system, conceivable as distinct, Supply and demand with
respect to particular commodities must be understood to mean supply and demand at a given price;
and thus we are introduced to the ideas of market price and normal price (as, following Cherbuliez,
he terms what Smith less happily called natural price). Normal price again leads to the consideration
of cost of production, and here, against Mill and others, he denies that profit and wages enter into
cost of production; in other words, he asserts what Senior (whom he does not name) had said
before him, though he had not consistently carried out the nomenclature, that cost of production is
the sum of labour and abstinence necessary to production, wags and profits being the remuneration
of sacrifice and not elements of it. But, it may well be asked, How can an amount of labour be added
to an amount of abstinence? Must not wages and profits be taken as "measures of cost "? By
adhering to the conception of, "sacrifice" he exposes the emptiness of the assertion that "dear
labour is the great obstacle to the extension of British trade " --a sentence in which "British trade "
means capitalists' profits. At this point we are introduced to a doctrine now first elaborated, though
there are indications of it in Mill, of whose theory of international values it is in fact an extension. In
foreign trade cost of production, in Cairnes's sense, does not regulate values, because it cannot
perform that function except under a regime of effective competition, and between different
countries effective competition does not exist. But, Cairnes asks, to what extent does it exist in
domestic industries? So far as capital is concerned, he thinks the condition is sufficiently fulfilled
over the whole field--a position, let it be said in passing, which he does not seem to make out, if we
consider the practical immobility of most invested, as distinct from disposable, capital. But in the
case of labour the requisite competition takes place only within certain social, or rather industrial,
strata. The world of industry may be divided into a series of superposed groups, and these groups
are practically: "non-competing," the disposable labour in any one of them being rarely capable of
choosing its field in a higher.(57) The law that cost of production determines price cannot, therefore,
be absolutely stated respecting domestic any more than respecting international exchange,. as it
fails for the latter universally, so it fails for the former as between non-competing groups. The law
that holds between these is similar to that governing international values, which may be called the
equation of reciprocal demand. Such a state of relative prices will establish itself amongst the
products of these groups as shall enable that portion of the products of each group which is applied
to the purchase of the products of all other groups to discharge its liabilities towards those other
groups. The reciprocal demand of the groups determines the " average relative level " of prices
within each group; whilst cost of production regulates the distribution of price among the individual
products of each group This theorem is perhaps of no great practical value; but the tendency of the
whole investigation is to attenuate the importance of cost of production as a regulator of normal
price, and so to show that yet another of the accepted doctrines of the science had been
propounded in too rigid and absolute a form. As to market price, the formula by which Mill had
defined it as the price which equalises demand and supply Cairnes shows to be an identical
proposition, and he defines it as the price which most advantageously adjusts the existing supply to
the existing demand pending the coming forward of fresh supplies from the sources of production.
His second part is chiefly remarkable for his defence of what is known as the wages fund doctrine,
to which we adverted when speaking of Senior.(58) Mill had given up this doctrine, having been
convinced by Thornton that it was erroneous; but Cairnes refused to follow his leader, who, as he
believes, ought not to have been convinced.(59) After having given what is certainly a fallacious
reply to Longe's criticism of the expression "average rate of wages," he proceeds to vindicate the
doctrine in question by the consideration that the amount of a nation's wealth devoted at any tie to
the payment of wages--if the character of the national industries and the methods of production
employed remain the same--is in a definite relation to the amount of its general capital; the latter
being given, the former is also given. In illustrating his view of the subject, he insists on the principle
(true in the main, but too absolutely formulated by Mill) that " demand for commodities is not
demand for labour," It is not necessary here to follow his investigation, for his reasoning has not
satisfied his successors, with the exception of Fawcett, and the question of wages is now commonly
treated without reference to a supposed determinate wages fund, Cairnes next studies trades-
unionism in relation to wages, and arrives in substance at the conclusion that the only way in which
it can affect their rate is by accelerating an advance which must ultimately have taken place
independently of its action. He also takes occasion to refute Mr. (now Lord) Brassey's supposed law
of a uniform cost of labour in every part of the world. Turning to consider the material prospects of
the working classes, he examines the question of the changes which may be expected in the
amount and partition of the fund out gf which abstinence and labour are remunerated. He here
enunciates the principle (which had been, however, stated before him by Ricardo and Senior) that
the increased productiveness of industry will not affect either profit or wages unless it cheapen the
commodities which the labourer consumes. These latter. being mostly commodities of which raw
produce is the only or principal element, their cost of production, notwithstanding improvements in
knowledge and art, will increase unless the numbers of the labouring class be steadily kept in
check; and hence the possibility of elevating the condition of the labourer is confined within very
narrow limits, if he continues to be a labourer only. The condition of any substantial and permanent
improvement in his lot is that he should cease to be a mere labourer--that profits should be brought
to reinforce the wages fund, which has a tendency, in the course of industrial progress, to decline
relatively to the general capital of a country. And hence Cairnes--abandoning the purely theoretic
attitude which he elsewhere represents as the only proper one for the economist-recommends the
system of so-called co-operation (that is, in fact, the abolition of the large capitalist) as offering to
the working classes " the sole means of escape from a harsh and hopeless destiny," and puts aside
rather contemptuously the opposition of the Positivists to this solution, which yet many besides the
Positivists, as, for example, Leslie and F, A. Walker, regard as chimerical.
The third part is devoted mainly to an exposition of Ricardo' s doctrine of the conditions of
international trade and Mill's theory of international values. The former Cairnes modifies by
introducing his idea of the partial influence of reciprocal demand, as distinguished from cost of
production, on the regulation of domestic prices, and founds on this rectification an interesting
account of that connection between the wages prevailing in a country and the character and course
of its external trade. He emends Mill's statement, which represented the produce of a country as
exchanging for that of other countries at such values " as are required in order that the whole of her
exports may exactly pay for the whole of her imports " by substituting for the latter phrase the
condition that each country should by means of her exports discharge all her foreign liabilities-in
other words, by introducing the consideration of the balance of debts. This idea was not new. it had
been indicated by John Leslie Foster as early as 1804,(60) and was touched on by Mill himself; but
Cairnes expounds it well; and it is important as clearing away common misconceptions, and
sometimes removing groundless alarms.(61) Passing to the question of free trade, he disposes of
some often-repeated protectionist arguments, and in particular refutes the American allegation of
the inability of the highly-paid labour of that country to compete with the "pauper labour " of Europe.
He is not so successful in meeting the "political argument," founded on the admitted importance for
civilization of developing diversified national industries; and he meets only by one of the highly
questionable commonplaces of the doctrinaire economists Mill's proposition that protection may
foster nascent industries really adapted to a country till they have struck root and are able to endure
the stress of foreign competition.
We have dwelt at some length on this work of Cairnes, not only because it presents the latest iorms
of several accepted economic doctrines, but also because it is, and, we believe, will remain, the last
important product of the old English school. The author at the outset expresses the hope that it will
strengthen, and add consistence to, the scientific fabric "built up by the labours of Adam Smith,
Malthus, Ricardo, and Mill." Whilst recognizing with him the great merits of Smith, and the real
abilities and services of his three successors here named, we cannot entertain the same opinion as
Cairnes respecting the permanance of the fabric they constructed. We hold that a new edifice is
required, incorporating indeed many of the materials of the old, but planned on different ideas and in
some respects with a view to different ends--above all, resting on different philosophic foundations,
and having relation in its whole design to the more comprehensive structure of which it will form but
one department, namely, the general science of society.
Cairnes's Slave Power, (1862) was the most valuable work which appeared on the subject of the
great American conflict.
FRANCE
All the later European schools presuppose-in part adopting, in part criticising--the work of the
English economists from Smith(62) to Ricardo and the Epigoni. The German school has had in a
greater degree than any other a movement of its own-following, at least in its more recent period, an
original method, and tending to special and characteristic conclusions. The French school, on the
other hand,-if we omit the Socialists, who do not here come under consideration, -has in the main
reproduced the doctrines of the leading English thinkers,--stopping short, however, in general of the
extremes of Ricardo and his disciples. In the field of exposition the French are unrivalled; and in
political economy they have produced a series of more or less remarkable systematic treatises, text-
books, and compendiums, at the head of which stands the celebrated work of J. B. Say. But the
number of seminal minds which have appeared in French economic literature of writers who have
contributed important truths, introduced improvements of method, or presented the phenomena
under new light--has not been large. Sismondi, Dunoyer, and Bastiat will deserve our attention, as
being the most important of those who occupy independent positions (whether permanently tenable
or not), if we pass over for the present the great philosophical renovation of Auguste Comte, which
comprehended actually or potentially all the branches of sociological inquiry. Before estimating the
labours of Bastiat. we shall find it desirable to examine the views of Carey, the most renowned of
American economists, with which the latest teachings of the ingenious and eloquent Frenchman
are, up to a certain point, in remarkable agreement. Cournot, too, must find a place among the
French writers of this period, as the chief representative of the conception of a mathematical method
in political economy.
Of Jean Baptiste Say (1767-1832) Ricardo says "He was the first, or among the first, of Continental
writers who justly appreciated and applied the principles of Smith, and has done more than all other
Continental writers taken together to recommend that enlightened and beneficial system to the
nations of Europe." The Wealth of Nations in the original language was placed in Say's hands by
Clavière, afterwards minister, then director of the assurance society of which Say was a clerk; and
the book made a powerful impression on him. Long afterwards, when Dupont de Nemours
complained of his injustice to the physiocrats, and claimed him as, through Smith, a spiritual
grandson of Quesnay and nephew of Turgot, he replied that he had learned to read in the writings of
the mercantile school, had learned to think in those of Quesnay and his followers, but that it was in
Smith that he had learned to seek the causes and the effects of social phenomena in the nature of
things, and to arrive at this last by a scrupulous analysis. His Traits d'Économie Politique (1803) was
essentially founded on Smith's work, but he aimed at arranging the materials in a more logical and
instructive order.(63) He has the French art of easy and lucid exposition, though his facility
sometimes degenerates into superficiality; and hence his book became popular, both directly and
through translations obtained a wide circulation, and diffused rapidly through the civilized world the
doctrines of the master. Say's knowledge of common life, says Roscher, was equal to Smith's; but
he falls far below him in living insight into larger political phenomena, and he carefully eschews
historical and philosophical explanations. He is sometimes strangely shallow, as when he says that
"the best tax is that smallest in amount." He appears not to have much claim to the position of an
original thinker in political economy. Ricardo, indeed, speaks of him as having "enriched the
science, by several discussions, original, accurate, and profound." What he had specially in view in
using these words was what is, perhaps rather pretentiously, called Say's théorie des débouchés,
with his connected disproof of the possibility of a universal glut. The theory amounts simply to this,
that buying is also selling, and that it is by producing that we are enabled to purchase the products
of others. Several distinguished economists, especially Malthus and Sismondi, in consequence
chiefly of a misinterpretation of the phenomena of commercial crises, maintained that there might be
general over-supply or excess of all commodities above the demand. This Say rightly denied. A
particular branch of production may, it must indeed be admitted, exceed the existing capabilities of
the market ; but, if we remember that supply is demand, that commodities are purchasing power, we
cannot accept the doctrine of the possibility of a universal glut without holding that we can have too
much of everythingthat "all men can be so fully provided with the precise articles they desire as to
afford no market for each other's superfluities." Whatever services, however, Say may have
rendered by original ideas on those or other subjects, his great merit is certainly that of a
propagandist and populariser.
The imperial police would not permit a second edition of his work to be issued without the
introduction of changes which, with noble independence, he refused to make; and that edition did
not therefore appear till 1814. Three other editions were published during the life of the authorin
1817, 1819, and 1826. In 1828 Say published a second treatise, Cours complet d'éonomie Politique
pratique, which contained the substance of his lectures at the Conservatoire des Arts et Métiers and
at the Collége de France. `Whilst in his earlier treatise he had kept within the narrow limits of strict
economics, in his later work he enlarged the sphere of discussion, introducing in particular many
considerations respecting the economic influence of social institutions.
Jean Charles L. Simonde de Sismondi (17731842), author of the Histoire des Républiques
Italienises dis moyen âge, represents in the economic field a protest, founded mainly on
humanitarian sentiment, against the dominant doctrines He wrote first a treatise De la Richesse
Commerciale (1803), in which he followed strictly the principles of Adam Smith. But he afterwards
came to regard these principles as insufficient and requiring modification. He contributed an article
on political economy to the Edinburgh Encyclopeadia, in which his new views were partially
indicated. They were fully developed in his principal econcmic work, Nouveaux Principes
d'Économie Politique, ou de la Richesse dans ses rapports avec la Population (1819; 2d ed., 1827).
This work, as he tells us, was not received with favour by economists, a fact which he explains by
the consideration that he had "attacked an orthodoxyan enterprise dangerous in philosophy as in
religion." According to his view, the science, as commonly understood, was too much of a mere
chrematistic: it studied too exclusively the means of increasing wealth, and not sufficiently the use of
this wealth for producing general happiness. The practical system founded on it tended, as he
believed, not only to make the rich richer, but to make the poor poorer and more dependent; and he
desired to fix attention on the question of distribution as by far the most important, especially in the
social circum- stances of recent times.
The personal union in Sismondi of three nationalities, the Italian, the French, and the Swiss, and his
comprehensive historical studies, gave him a special largeness of view; and he was filled with a
noble sympathy for the suffering members of society. He stands nearer to socialism than any other
French economist proper, but it is only in sentiment, not in opinion, that he approximates to it; he
does not recommend any socialistic scheme. On the contrary, he declares in a memorable passage
that, whilst he sees where justice lies, he must confess himself unable to suggest the means of
realising it in practice; the division of the fruits of industry between those who are united in their
production appears to him vicious; but it is, in his judgment, almost beyond human power to
conceive any system of property absolutely different from that which is known to us by experience.
He goes no further than protesting, in view of the great evils which he saw around him, against the
doctrine of laisser faire, and invoking, somewhat vaguely, the intervention of Governments to
regulate the progress of wealth and to protect the weaker members of the community.
His frank confession of impotence, far wiser and more honourable than the suggestion of precipitate
and dangerous remedies, or of a recurrence to outworn mediaeval institutions, has not affected the
reputation of the work. A prejudice was indeed early created against it in consequence of its partial
harmony of tone, though, as we have seen, not of policy, with socialism, which was then beginning
to show its strength, as well as by the rude way in which his descriptions of the modern industrial
system, especially as it existed in England, disturbed the complacent optimism of some members of
the so-called orthodox school. These treated the book with ill-disguised contempt, and Bastiat spoke
of it as preaching an économie politique à rebours. But it has held its place in the literature of the
science, and is now even more interesting than when it first appeared, because in our time there is a
more general disposition, instead of denying or glossing over the serious evils of industrial society,
to face and remove or at least mitigate them. The laisser faire doctrine, too, has been discredited in
theory and abandoned in practice; and we are ready to admit Sismondi's view of the State as a
power not mere intrusted with the maintenance of peace, but charged also with the mission of
extending the benefits of the social union and of modern progress as widely as possible through all
classes of the community. Yet the impression which his treatise leaves behind it is a discouraging
one; and this because he regards as essentially evil many things which seem to be the necessary
results of the development of industry. The growth of a wealthy capitalist class and of manufacture
on the great scale, the rise of a vast body of workers who live by their labour alone, the extended
application of machines, large landed properties cultivated with the aid of the most advanced
appliancesall these he dislikes and deprecates; but they appear to be inevitable. The problem is,
how to regulate and moralise the system they imply; but we must surely accept it in principle, unless
we aim at a thorough social revolution. Sismondi may be regarded as the precursor of the German
economists known under the inexact designation of Socialists of the Chair; but their writings are
much more hopeful and inspiring.
To the subject of population he devotes special care, as of great importance for the welfare of the
working classes. So far as agriculturists are concerned, he thinks the system of what he calls
patriarchal exploitation, where the cultivator is also proprietor, and is aided by his family in tilling the
land a law of equal division among the natural heirs being apparently presupposedthe one which is
most efficacious in preventing an undue increase of the population. The father is, in such a case,
able distinctly to estimate the resources available for his children, and to determine the stage of sub-
division which would necessitate the descent of the family from the material and social position it
had previously occupied. When children beyond this limit are born, they do not marry, or they
choose amongst their number one to continue the race. This is the view which, adopted by J. S. Mill,
makes so great a figure in the too favourable presentation by that writer of the system of peasant
proprietors.
In no French economic writer is greater force or general solidity of thought to be found than in
Charles Dunoyer (17861862), author of La Liberté du Travail (1845; the substance of the first
volume had appeared under a different title in 1825), honourably known for his integrity and
independence under the régime of the Restoration. What makes him of special importance in the
history of the science is his view of its philosophical constitution and method. With respect to
method, he strikes the keynote at the very outset in the words "rechercher expérimentalement," and
in professing to build on "les données de l'observation et de l'expérience." He shows a marked
tendency to widen economics into a general science of society, expressly describing political
economy as having for its province the whole order of things which results from the exercise and
development of the social forces. This larger study is indeed better named Sociology; and economic
studies are better regarded as forming one department of it. But the essential circumstance is that,
in Dunoyer's treatment of his great subject, the widest intellectual, moral, and political
considerations are inseparably combined with purely economic ideas. It must not be supposed that
by liberty, in the title of his work, is meant merely freedom from legal restraint or administrative
interference; he uses it to express whatever tends to give increased efficiency to labour. He is thus
led to discuss all the causes of human progress, and to exhibit them in their historical working.
Treating, in the first part, of the influence of external conditions, of race, and of culture on liberty in
this wider sense, he proceeds to divide all productive effort into two great classes, according as the
action is exercised on things or on men, and censures the economists for having restricted their
attention to the former. He studies in his second and third parts respectively the conditions of the
efficiency of these two forms of human exertion. In treating of economic life, strictly so called, he
introduces his fourfold division of material industry, in part adopted by J. S. Mill, as "(1) extractive,
(2) voiturière, (3) manufacturièure, (4) agricole," a division which is useful for physical economics,
but will always, when the larger social aspect of things is considered, be inferior to the more
commonly accepted one into agricultural, manufacturing, and commercial industry, banking being
supposed as common president and regulator. Dunoyer, having in view only action on material
objects, relegates banking, as well as commerce proper, to the separate head of exchange, which,
along with association and gratuitous transmission (whether inter vivos or mortis causa), he classes
apart as being, not industries, in the same sense with the occupations named, but yet functions
essential to the social economy. The industries which act on man he divides according as they
occupy themselves with (1) the amelioration of our physical nature, (2) the culture of our imagination
and sentiments, (3) the education of our intelligence, and (4) the improvement of our moral habits;
and he proceeds accordingly to study the social offices of the physician, the artist, the educator, and
the priest. We meet in Dunoyer the ideas afterwards emphasised by Bastiat that the real subjects of
human exchange are services; that all value is due to human activity; that the powers of nature
always render a gratuitous assistance to the labour of man and that the rent of land is really a form
of interest on invested capital. Though he had disclaimed the task of a practical adviser in the often-
quoted sentence"Je n'impose rien; je ne propose même rien; j'exposé," he finds himself, like all
economists, unable to abstain from offering counsel. And his policy is opposed to any state
interference with industry. Indeed he preaches in its extreme rigour the laisser faire doctrine, which
he maintains principally on the ground that the spontaneous efforts of the individual for the
improvement of his condition, by developing foresight, energy, and perseverance, are the most
efficient means of social culture. But he certainly goes too far when he represents the action of
Governments as normally always repressive and never directive. He was doubtless led into this
exaggeration by his opposition to the artificial organizations of labour proposed by so many of his
contemporaries, against which he had to vindicate the principle of competition; but his criticism of
these schemes took, as Comte remarks, too absolute a character, tending to the perpetual
interdiction of a true systematisation of industry.(64)
AMERICA
At this point it will be convenient to turn aside and notice the doctrines of the American economist
Carey. Not much had been done before him in the science by citizens of the United States.
Benjamin Franklin, otherwise of world-wide renown, was author of a number of tracts, in most of
which he merely enforces practical lessons of industry and thrift, but in some throws out interesting
theoretic ideas. Thus, fifty years before Smith, he suggested (as Petty, however, had already done)
human labour as the true measure of value (Modest Inquiry into the Nature and Necessity of a
Paper Currency, 1721), and in his Observations concerning the Increase of Mankind (1751) he
expresses views akin to those of Malthus. Alexander Hamilton, secretary of the treasury, in 1791
presented in his official capacity to the House of Representatives of the United States a Report on
the measures by which home manufactures could be promoted.(65) In this document he gives a
critical account of the theory of the subject, represents Smith's system of free trade as possible in
practice only if adopted by all nations simultaneously, ascribes to manufactures a greater
productiveness than to agriculture, and seeks to refute the objections against the development of
the former in America founded on the want of capital, the high rate of wages, and the low price of
land. The conclusion at which he arrives is that for the creation of American manufactures a system
of moderate protective duties was necessary, and he proceeds to describe the particular features of
such a system. There is some reason to believe that the German economist List, of whom we shall
speak hereafter, was influenced by Hamilton's work, having, during his exile from his native country,
resided in the United States.
Henry Charles Carey (17931879), son of an American citizen who had emigrated from Ireland,
represents a reaction against the dispiriting character which the Smithian doctrines had assumed in
the hands of Malthus and Ricardo. His aim was, whilst adhering to the individualistic economy, to
place it on a higher and surer basis, and fortify it against the assaults of socialism, to which some of
the Ricardian tenets had exposed it. The most comprehensive as well as mature exposition of his
views is contained in his Principles of Social Science (1859). Inspired with the optimistic sentiment
natural to a young and rising nation with abundant undeveloped resources and an unbounded
outlook towards the future, he seeks to show that there exists, independently of human wills, a
natural system of economic laws, which is essentially beneficent, and of which the increasing
prosperity of the whole community, and especially of the working classes, is the spontaneous
result,capable of being defeated only by the ignorance or perversity of man resisting or impeding its
action. He rejects the Malthusian doctrine of population, maintaining that numbers regulate them-
selves sufficiently in every well-governed society, and that their pressure on subsistence
characterises the lower, not the more advanced, stages of civilization. He rightly denies the
universal truth, for all stages of cultivation, of the law of diminishing returns from land. His
fundamental theoretic position relates to the antithesis of wealth and value.
Wealth had been by most economists confounded with the sum of exchange values; even Smith,
though at first distinguishing them, afterwards allowed himself to fall into this error. Ricardo had,
indeed, pointed out the difference, but only towards the end of his treatise, in the body of which
value alone is considered. The later English economists had tended to regard their studies as
conversant only with exchange; so far had this proceeded that Whately had proposed for the
science the name of Catallactics. When wealth is considered as what it really is, the sum of useful
products, we see that it has its origin in external nature as supplying both materials and physical
forces, and in human labour as appropriating and adapting those natural materials and forces.
Nature gives her assistance gratuitously; labour is the sole foundation of value. The less we can
appropriate and employ natural forces in any production the higher the value of the product, but the
less the addition to our wealth in proportion to the labour expended. Wealth, in its true sense of the
sum of useful things, is the measure of the power we have acquired over nature, whilst the value of
an object expresses the resistance of nature which labour has to overcome in order to produce the
object. Wealth steadily increases in the course of social progress; the exchange value of objects, on
the other hand, decreases. Human intellect and faculty of social combination secure increased
command over natural powers, and use them more largely in production, whilst less labour is spent
in achieving each result, and the value of the product accordingly falls. The value of the article is not
fixed by its Cost of production in the past; what really determines it is the cost which is necessary for
its reproduction under the present conditions of knowledge and skill. The dependence of value on
cost, so interpreted, Carey holds to be universally true; whilst Ricardo maintained it only with respect
to objects capable of indefinite multiplication, and in particular did not regard it as applicable to the
case of land. Ricardo saw in the productive powers of land a free gift of nature which had been
monopolised by a certain number of persons, and which became, with the increased demand for
food, a larger and larger value in the hands of its possessors. To this value, however, as not being
the result of labour, the owner, it might be maintained, had no rightful claim; he could not justly
demand a payment for what was done by the "original and indestructible powers of the soil." But
Carey held that land, as we are concerned with it in industrial life, is really an instrument of
production which has been formed as such by man, and that its value is due to the labour expended
on it in the past,though measured, not by the sum of that labour, but by the labour necessary under
existing conditions to bring new land to the same stage of productiveness. He studies the
occupation and reclamation of land with peculiar advantage as an American, for whom the traditions
of first settlement are living and fresh, and before whose eyes the process is indeed still going on.
The difficulties of adapting a primitive soil to the work of yielding organic products for man's use can
be lightly estimated only by an inhabitant of a country long under cultivation. It is, in Carey's view,
the overcoming of these difficulties by arduous and continued effort that entitles the first occupier of
land to his property in the soil. Its present value forms a very small proportion of the cost expended
on it, because it represents only what would be required, with the science and appliances of our
time, to bring the land from its primitive into its present state. Property in land is therefore only a
form of invested capital a quantity of labour or the fruits of labour permanently incorporated with the
soil; for which, like any other capitalist, the owner is compensated by a share of the produce. He is
not rewarded for what is done by the powers of nature, and society is in no sense defrauded by his
sole possession. The so-called Ricardian theory of rent is a speculative fancy, contradicted by all
experience. Cultivation does not in fact, as that theory supposes, begin with the best, and move
downwards to the poorer soils in the order of their inferiority.(66) The light and dry higher lands are
first cultivated; and only when population has become dense and capital has accumulated, are the
low- lying lands, with their greater fertility, but also with their morasses, inundations, and miasmas,
attacked and brought into occupation. Rent, regarded as a proportion of the produce, sinks, like all
interest on capital, in process of time, but, as an absolute amount, increases. The share of the
labourer increases, both as a proportion and an absolute amount. And thus the interest of these
different social classes are in harmony.
But, Carey proceeds to say, in order that this harmonious progress may be realised, what is taken
from the land must be given back to it. All the articles derived from it are really separated parts of it,
which must be restored on pain of its exhaustion. Hence the producer and the consumer must be
close to each other; the products must not be exported to a foreign country in exchange for its
manufactures, and thus go to enrich as manure a foreign soil. In immediate exchange value the
landowner may gain by such exportation, but the productive powers of the land will suffer. And thus
Carey, who had set out as an earnest advocate of free trade, arrives at the doctrine of protection:
the "co-ordinating power" in society must intervene to prevent private advantage from working public
mischief.(67) He attributes his conversion on the question to his observation of the effects of liberal
and protective tariffs respectively on American prosperity. This observation, he says, threw him back
on theory, and led him to see that the intervention referred to might be necessary to remove (as he
phrases it) the obstacles to the progress of younger communities created by the action of older and
wealthier nations. But it seems probable that the influence of List's writings, added to his own deep-
rooted and hereditary jealousy and dislike of English predominance, had something to do with his
change of attitude.
The practical conclusion at which he thus arrived, though it is by no means in contradiction to the
doctrine of the existence of natural economic laws, accords but ill with his optimistic scheme; and
another economist, Frederic Bastiat, accepting his fundamental ideas, applied himself to remove the
foreign accretion, as he regarded it, and to preach the theory of spontaneous social harmonies in
relation with the practice of free trade as its legitimate outcome.(68) FRANCE(continued)
Bastiat (1801-1850), though not a profound thinker, was a brilliant and popular writer on economic
questions. Though he always had an inclination for such studies, he was first impelled to the active
propagation of his views by his earnest sympathy with the English anti-corn-law agitation. Naturally
of an ardent temperament, he threw himself with zeal into the free-trade controversy, through which
he hoped to influence French economic policy, and published in 1845 a history of the struggle under
the title of Cobden et La Ligue. In 184548 appeared his Sophismes économiques (Eng. trans. by G.
R. Porter, 1849, and by P. J. Stirling, 1873), in which he exhibited his best qualities of mind. Though
Cairnes goes too far in comparing this work with the Lettres Provinciales, it is certainly marked by
much liveliness, point, and vigour. But to expose the absurdities of the ordinary protectionism was
no difficult task; it is only in such a form as the policy assumed in the scheme of List, as purely
provisional and preparatory, that it deserves and demands consideration. After the revolution of
1848, which for a time put an end to the free- trade movement in France, the efforts of Bastiat were
directed against the socialists. Besides several minor pieces possessing the same sort of merit as
the Sophismes, he produced, with a view to this controversy, his most ambitious as well as
characteristic work, the Harmonies Économiques (Eng. trans. by P. J. Stirling, 1860). Only the first
volume was published; it appeared in 1850, and its author died in the same year. Since then the
notes and sketches which he had prepared s materials towards the production of the second
volume have been given to the public in the collected edition of his writings (by Paillottet, with Life by
Fontenay, 7 vols.), and we can thus gather what would have been the spirit and substance of the
later portions of the book.
It will always be historically interesting as the last incarnation of thoroughgoing economic optimism.
This optimism, recurring to its first origin, sets out from theological considerations, and Bastiat is
commended by his English translator for treating political economy "in connection with final causes."
The spirit of the work is to represent "all principles, all motives, all springs of action, all interests, as
co-operating towards a grand final result which humanity will never reach, but to which it will always
increasingly tend, namely, the indefinite approximation of all classes towards a level, which steadily
rises,in other words, the equalisation of individuals in the general amelioration."
What claimed to be novel and peculiar in his scheme was principally his theory of value. Insisting on
the idea that value does not denote anything inherent in the objects to which it is attributed, he
endeavoured to show that it never signifies anything but the ratio of two "services.'' This view he
develops with great variety and felicity of illustration. Only the mutual services of human beings,
according to him, possess-value and can claim a retribution; the assistance given by nature to the
work of production is always purely gratuitous, and never enters into price. Economic progress, as,
for example, the improvement and larger use of machinery, tends perpetually to transfer more and
more of the elements of utility from the domain of property, and therefore of value, into that of
community, or of universal and unpurchased enjoyment. It will be observed that this theory is
substantially identical with Carey's, which had been earlier propounded; and the latter author in so
many words alleges it to have been taken from him without acknowledgment. It has not perhaps
been sufficiently attended to that very similar views are found in Dunoyer, of whose work Bastiat
spoke as exercising a powerful influence on "the restoration of the science," and whom Fontenay,
the biographer of Bastiat, tells us he recognised as one of his masters, Charles Comte(69) being the
other.
The mode which has just been explained of conceiving industrial action and industrial progress is
interesting and instructive so far as it is really applicable, but it was unduly generalised. Cairnes has
well pointed out that Bastiat's theoretic soundness was injuriously affected by his habit of studying
doctrines with a direct view to contemporary social and political controversies. He was thus
predisposed to accept views which appeared to lend a sanction to legitimate and valuable
institutions, and to reject those which seemed to him to lead to dangerous consequences. His
constant aim is, as he himself expressed it, to "break the weapons " of anti-social reasoners "in their
hands," and this preoccupation interferes with the single-minded effort towards the attainment of
scientific truth. The creation or adoption of his theory of value was inspired by the wish to meet the
socialistic criticism of property in land; for the exigencies of this controversy it was desirable to be
able to show that nothing is ever paid for except personal effort. His view of rent was, therefore, so
to speak, f ore- ordained, though it may have been suggested, as indeed the editor of his
posthumous fragments admits by the writings of Carey. He held, with the American author, that rent
is purely the reward of the pains and expenditure of the landlord or his predecessors in the process
of converting the natural soil into a farm by clearing, draining, fencing, and the other species of
permanent improvements.(70) He thus gets rid of the (so-called) Ricardian doctrine, which was
accepted by the socialists, and by them used for the purpose of assailing the institution of landed
property, or, at least, of supporting a claim of compensation to the community for the appropriation
of the land by the concession of the "right to labour." As Cairnes has said,(71) "what Bastiat did was
this: having been at infinite pains to exclude gratuitous gifts of nature from the possible elements of
value, and pointedly identified" [rather, associated] "the phenomenon with `human effort' as its
exclusive source, he designates human effort by the term `service,' and then employs this term to
admit as sources of value those very gratuitous natural gifts the exclusion of which in this capacity
constituted the essence of his doctrine." The justice of this criticism will be apparent to any one who
considers the way in which Bastiat treats the question of the value of a diamond. That what is paid
for in most cases of human dealings is effort no one can dispute. But it is surely a reductio ad
absurdum of his theory of value, regarded as a doctrine of universal application, to represent the
price of a diamond which has been accidentally found as remuneration for the effort of the finder in
appropriating and transmitting it. And, with respect to land, whilst a large part of rent, in the popular
sense, must be explained as interest on capital, it is plain that the native powers of the soil are
capable of appropriation, and that then a price can be demanded and will be paid for their use.
Bastiat is weak on the philosophical side; he is filled with the ideas of theological teleology, and is
led by these ideas to form a priori opinions of what existing facts and laws must necessarily be. And
the jus nature, which, like metaphysical ideas generally, has its root in theology, is as much a
postulate with him as with the physiocrats. Thus, in his essay on Free Trade, he says:"Exchange is
a natural right like property. Every citizen who has created or acquired a product ought to have the
option of either applying it immediately to his own use or ceding it to whosoever on the surface of
the globe consents to give him in exchange the object of his desires." Something of the same sort
had been said by Turgot; and in his time this way of regarding things was excusable, and even
provisionally useful; but in the middle of the 19th century it was time that it should be seen through
and abandoned
Bastiat had a real enthusiasm for a science which he thought destined to render great services to
mankind, and he seems to have believed intensely the doctrines which gave a special colour to his
teaching. If his optimistic exaggerations favoured the propertied classes, they certainly were not
prompted by self-interest or servility. But they are exaggerations; and, amidst the modern conflicts of
capital and labour, his perpetual assertion of social harmonies is the cry of "peace, peace," where
there is no peace. The freedom of industry, which he treated as a panacea, has undoubtedly
brought with it great benefits; but a sufficient experience has shown that it is inadequate to solve the
social problem. How can the advocates of economic revolution be met by assuring them that
everything in the natural economy is harmoniousthat, in fact, all they seek for already exists? A
certain degree of spontaneous harmony does indeed exist, for society could not continue without it,
but it is imperfect and precarious; the question is, How can we give to it the maximum of
completeness and stability?
Augustin Cournot (18011877) appears to have been the first(72) who, with a competent knowledge
of both subjects, endeavoured to apply mathematics to the treatment of economic questions. His
treatise entitled Recherches sur les Principes Mathématiques de La Théorie des Richesses was
published in 1838. He mentions in it only one previous enterprise of the same kind (though there
had in fact been others)that, namely, of Nicolas François Canard, whose book, published in 1802,
was crowned by the Institute, though "its principles were radically false as well as erroneously
applied." Notwithstanding Cournot's just reputation as a writer on mathematics, the Recherches
made little impression. The truth seems to be that his results are in some cases of little importance,
in others of questionable correctness, and that, in the abstractions to which he has recourse in order
to facilitate his calculations, an essential part of the real conditions of the problem is sometimes
omitted. His pages abound in symbols representing unknown functions, the form of the function
being left to be ascertained by observation of facts, which he does not regard as a part of his task,
or only some known properties of the undetermined function being used as bases for deduction.
Jevons includes in his list of works in which a mathematical treatment of economics is adopted a
second treatise which Cournot published in 1863, with the title Principes de La Théorie des
Richesses. But in reality, in the work so named, which is written with great ability, and contains
much forcible reasoning in opposition to the exaggerations of the ordinary economists, the
mathematical method is abandoned, and there is not an algebraical formula in the book. The author
admits that the public has always shown a repugnance to the use of mathematical symbols in
economic discussion, and, though he thinks they might be of service in facilitating exposition, fixing
the ideas, and suggesting further developments, he acknowledges that a grave danger attends their
use. The danger, according to him, consists in the probability that an undue value may be attached
to the abstract hypotheses from which the investigator sets out, and which enable him to construct
his formulae. And his practical conclusion is that mathematical processes should be employed only
with great precaution, or even not employed at all if the public judgment is against them, for "this
judgment," he says, "has its secret reasons, almost always more sure than those which determine
the opinions of individuals." It is an obvious consideration that the acceptance of unsound or one-
sided abstract principles as the premises of argument does not depend on the use of mathematical
forms, though it is possible that the employment of the latter may by association produce an illusion
in favour of the certainty of those premises. But the great objection to the use of mathematics in
economic reasoning is that it is necessarily sterile. If we examine the attempts which have been
made to employ it, we shall find that the fundamental conceptions on which the deductions are
made to rest are vague, indeed metaphysical, in their character. Units of animal or moral
satisfaction, of utility, and the like, are as foreign to positive science as a unit of normative faculty
would be; and a unit of value, unless we understand by value the quantity of one commodity
exchangeable under given conditions for another, is an equally indefinite idea. Mathematics can
indeed formulate ratios of exchange when they have once been observed; but it cannot by any
process of its own determine those ratios, for quantitative conclusions imply quantitative premises,
and these are wanting. There is then no future for this kind of study, and it is only waste of
intellectual power to pursue it. But the importance of mathematics as an educational introduction to
all the higher orders of research is not affected by this conclusion. The study of the physical
medium, or environment, in which economic phenomena take place, and by which they are affected,
requires mathematics as an instrument; and nothing can ever dispense with the didactic efficacy of
that science, as supplying the primordial type of rational investigation, giving the lively sentiment of
decisive proof, and disinclining the mind to illusory conceptions and sophistical combinations. And a
knowledge of at least the fundamental principles of mathematics is necessary to economists to keep
them right in their statements of doctrine, and prevent their enunciating propositions which have no
definite meaning. Even distinguished writers sometimes betray a serious deficiency in this respect;
thus they assert that one quantity" varies inversely as " another, when what is meant is that the sum
(not the product) of the two is constant; and they treat as capable of numerical estimation the
amount of an aggregate of elements which, differing in kind, cannot be reduced to a common
standard. As an example of the latter error, it may be mentioned that "quantity of labour," so often
spoken of by Ricardo, and in fact made the basis of his system, includes such various species of
exertion as will not admit of summation or comparison.
ITALY
The first Italian translation of the Wealth of Nations appeared in 1780. The most distinguished Italian
economist of the period here dealt with was, however, no disciple of Smith. This was Melehiorre
Gioja, author, besides statistical and other writings, of a voluminous work entitled Nuovo Prospetto
delle Scienze Economiche (6 vols., 181517; the work was never completed), intended to be an
encyclopaedia of all that had been taught by theorists, enacted by Governments, or effected by
populations in the field of public and private economy It is a learned and able treatise, but so
overladen with quotations and tables as to repel rather than attract readers. Gioja admired the
practical economic system of England, and enlarges on the advantages of territorial properties,
manufactures, and mercantile enterprises on the large as opposed to the small scale. He defends a
restrictive policy, and insists on the necessity of the action of the state as a guiding, supervising, and
regulating power in the industria] world. But he is in full sympathy with the sentiment of his age
against ecclesiastical domination and other mediaeval survivals. We can but very briefly notice
Romagnosi (d. 1835), who, by his contributions to periodical literature, and by his personal teaching,
greatly influenced the course of economic thought in Italy; Antonio Scialoja (Principii d'Economia
Sociale, 1840; and Carestia e Governo, 1853), an able advocate of free trade (d. 1877) Luigi
Cibrario, well known as the author of Economia Politica del medic evo (1839; 5th ed., 1861 : French
trans. by Barneaud, 1859), which is in fact a view of the whole social system of that period;
Girolamo Boccardo (b. 1829; Trattato Teorico-pratico di Economia Politica, 1853); the brilliant
controversialist Francesco Ferrara, professor at Turin from 1849 to 1858 (in whose school most of
the present Italian teachers of the science were, directly or indirectly, educated), a partisan of the
laisser faire doctrine in its most extreme form, and an advocate of the peculiar opinions of Carey
and Bastiat on the subject of rent; and, lastly, the Neapolitan minister Ludovico Bianchini (Principii
della Scienza del Ben Vivere Sociale, 1845 and 1855), who is remarkable as having followed in
some degree an historical direction, and asserted the principle of relativity, and who also dwelt on
the relations of economics with morals, by a due attention to which the Italian economists have,
indeed, in general been honourably distinguished.
SPAIN
The Wealth of Nations was translated into Spanish by J. A. Ortiz in 1794. It may perhaps have
influenced Gaspar de Jovellanos, who in 1795 presented to the council of Castile and printed in the
same year his celebrated Informe de La Sociedad Economica de Madrid en expediente de Ley
Agraria, which was a powerful plea for reform, especially in taxation and the laws affecting
agriculture, including those relating to the systems of entail and mortmain. An English version of this
memoir is given in the translation (1809) of Laborde's Spain, vol. iv. GERMANY
Roscher observes that Smith did not at first produce much impression in Germany.(73) He does not
appear to have been known to Frederick the Great; he certainly exercised no influence on him. Nor
did Joseph II take notice of his work. And of the minor German princes, Karl Friedrich of Baden, as
a physiocrat, would not be accessible to his doctrines. It was otherwise in the generation whose
principal activity belongs to the first decade of the 19th century. The Prussian statesmen who were
grouped round Stein had been formed as economists by Smith, as had also Gentz, intellectually the
most important man of the Metternich regime in Austria.
The first German expositors of Smith who did more than merely reproduce his opinions were
Christian Jacob Kraus (17531807), Georg Sartorius (17661828), and August Ferdinand Lüder
(17601819). They contributed independent views from different standpoints,the first from that of the
effect of Smith's doctrine on practical government, the second from that of its bearing on history, the
third from that of its relation to statistics. Somewhat later came Gottlieb Hufeland (17601817),
Johann Friedrich Eusebius Lotz (17711838), and Ludwig Heinrich von Jakob (17591827), who,
whilst essentially of the school of Smith, apply themselves to a revision of the fundamental
conceptions of the science. These authors did not exert anything like the wide influence of Say,
partly on account of the less attractive form of their writings, but chiefly because Germany had not
then, like France, a European audience. Julius von Soden (17541831) is largely founded on Smith,
whom, however, he criticises with undue severity, especially in regard to his form and arrangement;
the Wealth of Nations he describes as a series of precious fragments, and censures Smith for the
absence of a comprehensive view ofthis whole subject, and also as one-sidedly English in his
tendencies.
The highest form of the Smithian doctrine in Germany is represented by four distinguished names :
Karl Heinrich Rau (17921870), Friedrich Nebenius (17841857), Friedrich Benedict Wilhelm
Hermann (17951868), and Johann Hemrich von Thünen (17831850).
Rau's characteristic is "erudite thoroughness." His Lehrbuch (182632) is an encyclopaedia of all that
up to his time had appeared in Germany under the several heads of Volkswirthschaftslehre,
Volkswirthschaftspolitik, and Finanzwissenschaft. His book is rich in statistical observations, and is
particularly instructive on the economic effects of different geographical conditions. It is well adapted
for the teaching of public servants whose duties are connected with economics, and it was in fact
the source from which the German official world down to the seventies of the 19th century derived
its knowledge of the science. In his earlier period Rau had insisted on the necessity of a reform of
economic doctrine (Ansichten der Volkswirthschaft, 1821), and had tended towards relativity and the
historical method; but he afterwards conceived the mistaken notion that that method "only looked
into the past without studying the means of improving the present," and became himself purely
practical in the narrower sense of that word. He has the merit of having given a separate treatment
of Unternehmergewinn, or" wages of management." Nebenius, minister in Baden, who was largely
instrumental in the foundation of the Zollverein, was author of a highly esteemed monograph on
public credit (1820). The Staatswirthschafthiche Untersuchungen (1832; 2d ed., 1870) of Hermann
do not form a regular system, but treat a series of important special subjects. His rare technological
knowledge gave him a great advantage in dealing with some economic questions. He reviewed the
principal fundamental ideas of the science with great thoroughness and acuteness. "His strength,"
says Roscher, "lies in his clear, sharp, exhaustive distinction between the several elements of a
complex conception, or the several steps comprehended in a complex act." For keen analytical
power his German brethren compare him with Ricardo. But he avoids several one-sided views of the
English economist. Thus he places public spirit beside egoism as an economic motor, regards price
as not measured by labour only but as a product of several factors, and habitually contemplates the
consumption of the labourer, not as a part of the cost of production to the capitalist, but as the main
practical end of economics. Thünen is known principally by his remarkable work entitled Der Isolirte
Staat in Beziehung auf Landwirthschaft und Nationalökonomie (1826; 3d ed., 1875). In this treatise,
which is a classic in the political economy of agriculture, there is a rare union of exact observation
with creative imagination. With a view to exhibit the natural development of agriculture, he imagines
a state, isolated from the rest of the world, circular in form and of uniform fertility, without navigable
rivers or canals, with a single large city at its centre, which supplies it with manufactures and
receives in exchange for them its food-products, and proceeds to study the effect of distance from
this central market on the agricultural economy of the several concentric spaces which compose the
territory. The method, it will be seen, is highly abstract, but, though it may not be fruitful, it is quite
legitimate. The author is under no illusion blinding him to the unreality of the hypothetic case. The
supposition is necessary, in his view, in order to separate and consider apart one essential
conditionthat, namely, of situation with respect to the market. It was his intention (imperfectly
realised, however) to institute afterwards several different hypotheses in relation to his isolated
state, for the purpose of similarly studying other conditions which in real life are found in
combination or conflict. The objection to this method lies in the difficulty of the return from the
abstract study to the actual facts; and this is probably an insuperable one in regard to most of its
applications. The investigation, however, leads to trustworthy conclusions as to the conditions of the
succession of different systems of land economy. The book abounds in calculations relating to
agricultural expenditure and income, which diminish its interest to the general reader, though they
are considered valuable to the specialist. They embody the results of the practical experience of the
author on his estate of Tellow in Mecklenburg-Schwerin. Thünen was strongly impressed with the
danger of a violent conflict between the middle class and the proletariate, and studied earnestly the
question of wages, which he was one of the first to regard habitually, not merely as the price of the
commodity labour, but as the means of subsistence of the mass of the community. He arrived by
mathematical reasonings of some complexity at a formula which expresses the amount of "natural
wages" as = where a is the necessary expenditure of the labourer for subsistence, and p is the
product of his labour. To this formula he attributed so much importance that he directed it to be
engraved on his tomb. It implies that wages ought to rise with the amount of the product; and this
conclusion led him to establish on his estate a system of participation by the labourers in the profits
of farming, of which some account will be found in Mr. Sedley Taylor's Profit-sharing between
Capital and Labour (1884). Thünen deserves more attention than he has received in England; both
as a man and as a writer he was eminently interesting and original; and there is much in Der Isolirte
Staat and his other works that is awakening and suggestive.
Roscher recognizes what he calls a Germano-Russian (deutsch-russische) school of political
economy, represented principally by Heinrich Storch (17661825). Mercantilist principles had been
preached by a native (" autochthonen ") economist, Ivan Possoschkoff, in the time of Peter the
Great. The new ideas of the Smithian system were introduced into Russian by Christian Von
Schhizer (17741831) in his professorial lectures and in his Anfangsgründe der Staatswirthschaft,
oder die Lehre vom National-reichthume (18051807). Storch was instructor in economic science of
the future emperor Nicholas and his brother the grand- duke Michael, and the substance of his
lessons to them is contained in his Cours d'économie Politique (1815). The translation of this
treatise into Russian was prevented by the censorship; Rau published a German version of it, with
annotations, in 1819. It is a work of a very .high order of merit. The epithet" deutsch-russisch"
seems little applicable to Storch; as Roscher himself says, he follows mainly English and French
writersSay, Sismondi, Turgot, Bentham, Steuart, and Hume, but, above all, Adam Smith. His
personal position (and the same is true of Schi6zer) led him to consider economic doctrines in
connection with a stage of culture different from that of the Western populations amongst which they
had been formulated; this change of the point of view opened the door to relativity, and helped to
prepare the Historical method. Storch's study of the economic and moral effects of serfdom is
regarded as especially valuable. The general subjects with which he has particularly connected his
name are (1) the doctrine of immaterial commodities (or elements of national prosperity), such as
health, talent, morality, and the like; (2) the question of "productive" and "unproductive," as
characters of labour and of consumption, on which he disagreed with Smith and may have furnished
indications to Dunoyer; and (3) the differences between the revenue of nations and that of
individuals, on which he follows Lauderdale and is opposed to Say. The latter economist having
published at Paris (1823) a new edition of Storch's Cours, with criticisms sometimes offensive in
tone, he published by way of reply to some of Say's strictures what is considered his ripest and
scientifically most important work, Considérations sur la nature du Revenu National (1824;
translated into German by the author himself, 1825).
A distinct note of opposition to the Smithian economics was sounded in Germany by two writers,
who, setting out from somewhat different points of view, animated by different sentiments, and
favouring different practical systems, yet, so far as their criticisms are concerned, arrive at similar
conclusions; we mean Adam Müller and Friedrich List.
Adam Müller (17791829) was undoubtedly a man of real genius. In his principal work Élemente der
Staatskunst (1809), and his other writings, he represents a movement of economic thought which
was in relation with the (so-called) Romantic literature of the period. The reaction against
Smithianism of which he was the coryphaeus was founded on an attachment to the principles and
social system of the Middle Ages. It is possible that the political and historical ideas which inspire
him, his repugnance to contemporary liberalism, and his notions of regular organic development,
especially in relation to England, were in some degree imbibed from Edmund Burke, whose
Reflections on the Revolution in France had been translated into German by Friedrich Gentz, the
friend and teacher of Müller. The association of his criticisms with mediaeval prepossessions ought
not to prevent our recognizing the elements of truth which they contain.
He protests against the doctrine of Smith and against modern political economy in general on the
ground that it presents a mechanical, atomistic, and purely material conception of society, that it
reduces to nullity all moral forces and ignores the necessity of a moral order, that it is at bottom no
more than a theory of private property and private interests, and takes no account of the life of the
people as a whole in its national solidarity and historical continuity. Exclusive attention, he
complains, is devoted to the immediate production of objects possessing exchange value and to the
transitory existence of individuals; whilst to the maintenance of the collective production for future
generations, to intellectual products, powers, possessions and enjoyments, and to the State with its
higher tasks and aims, scarcely a thought is given. The truth is that nations are specialised
organisms with distinct principles of life, having definite individualities which determine the course of
their historical development. Each is through all time, one whole; and, as the present is the heir of
the past, it ought to keep before it constantly the permanent good of the community in the future.
The economic existence of a people is only one side or province of its entire activity, requiring to be
kept in harmony with the higher ends of society; and the proper organ to effect this reconciliation is
the State, which, instead of being merely an apparatus for the administration of justice, represents
the totality of the national life. The division of labour, Müller holds, is imperfectly developed by
Smith, who makes it to arise out of a native bent for truck or barter; whilst its dependence on
capitalon the labours and accumulations of past generationsis not duly emphasised, nor is the
necessary counterpoise and completion of the division of labour, in the principle of the national
combination of labour, properly brought out. Smith recognizes only material, not spiritual, capital; yet
the latter, represented in every nation by language, as the former by money, is a real national store
of experience, wisdom, good sense, and moral feeling, transmitted with increase by each generation
to its successor, and enables each generation to produce immensely more than by its own unaided
powers it could possibly do. Again, the system of Smith is one-sidedly British; if it is innocuous on
the soil of England, it is because in her society the old foundations on which the spiritual and
material life of the people can securely rest are preserved in the surviving spirit of feudalism and the
inner connection of the whole social systemthe national capital of laws, manners, reputation, and
credit, which has been handed down in its integrity in consequence of the insular position of the
country. For the continent of Europe a quite different system is necessary, in which, in place of the
sum of the private wealth of individuals being viewed as the primary object, the real wealth of the
nation and the production of national power shall be made to predominate, and along with the
division of labour its national union and concentrationalong with the physical, no less the intellectual
and moral, capital shall be embraced. In these leading traits of Müller's thought there is much which
foreshadows the more recent forms of German economic and sociological speculation, especially
those characteristic of the "Historical" school.
Another element of opposition was represented by Friedrich List (17891846), a man of great
intellectual vigour as well as practical energy, and notable as having powerfully contributed by his
writings to the formation of the German Zollverein. His principal work is entitled Das Nationale
System der Politischen Oekonomie (1841; 7th ed., 1883: Eng. trans., 1885). Though his practical
conclusions were different from Müller's, he was largely influenced by the general mode of thinking
of that writer, and by his strictures on the doctrine of Smith. It was particularly against the
cosmopolitan principle in the modern economic system that he protested, and against the absolute
doctrine of free trade, which was in harmony with that principle. He gave prominence to the National
idea, and insisted on the special requirements of each nation according to its circumstances and
especially to the degree of its development.
He refuses to Smith's system the title of the industrial, which he thinks more appropriate to the
mercantile system, and designates the former as "the exchange-value system." He denies the
parallelism asserted by Smith between the economic conduct proper to an individual and to a
nation, and holds that the immediate private interest of the separate members of the community will
not lead to the highest good of the whole. The nation is an existence, standing between the
individual and Humanity, and formed into a unity by its language, manners, historical development,
culture, and constitution. This unity is the first condition of the security, wellbeing, progress, and
civilization of the individual; and private economic interests, like all others, must be subordinated to
the maintenance, completion, and strengthening of the nationality. The nation having a continuous
life, its true wealth consistsand this is List's fundamental doctrinenot in the quantity of exchange-
values which it possesses, but in the full and many-sided development of its productive powers. Its
economic education, if we may so speak, is more important than the immediate production of
values, and it may be right that the present generation should sacrifice its gain and enjoyment to
secure the strength and skill of the future. In the sound and normal condition of a nation which has
attained economic maturity, the three productive powers of agriculture, manufactures, and
commerce should be alike developed. But the two latter factors are superior in importance, as
exercising a more effective and fruitful influence on the whole culture of the nation, as well as on its
independence. Navigation, railways, all higher technical arts, connect themselves specially with
these factors; whilst in a purely agricultural state there is a tendency to stagnation, absence of
enterprise, and the maintenance of antiquated prejudices. But for the growth of the higher forms of
industry all countries are not adaptedonly those of the temperate zones, whilst the torrid regions
have a natural monopoly in the production of certain raw materials; and thus between these two
groups of countries a division of labour and confederation of powers spontaneously takes place. List
then goes on to explain his theory of the stages of economic development through which the nations
of the temperate zone, which are furnished with all the necessary conditions, naturally pass, in
advancing to their normal economic state. These are (1) pastoral life, (2) agriculture, (3) agriculture
united with manufactures; whilst in the final stage agriculture, manufactures, and commerce are
combined. The economic task of the state is to bring into existence by legislative and administrative
action the conditions required for the progress of the nation through these stages. Out of this view
arises List's scheme of industrial politics. Every nation, according to him, should begin with free
trade, stimulating and improving its agriculture, by intercourse with richer and more cultivated
nations, importing foreign manufactures and exporting raw products. When it is economically so far
advanced that it can manufacture for itself, then a system of protection should be employed to allow
the home industries to develop themselves fully, and save them from being overpowered in their
earlier efforts by the competition of more matured foreign industries in the home market. When the
national industries have grown strong enough no longer to dread this competition, then the highest
stage of progress has been reached; free trade should again become the rule, and the nation be
thus thoroughly incorporated with the universal industrial union. In List's time, according to his view,
Spain, Portugal, and Naples were purely agricultural countries; Germany and the United States of
North America had arrived at the second stage, their manufactures being in process of
development. France was near the boundary of the third or highest stage, which England alone had
reached. For England, therefore, as well as for the agricultural countries first- named, free trade was
the right economic policy, but not for Germany or America. What a nation loses for a time in
exchange-values during the protective period she much more than gains in the long run in
productive power,the temporary expenditure being strictly analogous, when we place ourselves at
the point of view of the life of the nation, to the cost of the industrial education of the individual. The
practical conclusion which List drew for his own country was that she needed for her economic
progress an extended and conveniently bounded territory reaching to the sea- coast both on north
and south, and a vigorous expansion of manufactures and commerce, and that the way to the latter
lay through judicious protective legislation with a customs union comprising all German lands, and a
German marine with a Navigation Act. The national German spirit, striving after independence and
power through union, and the national industry, awaking from its lethargy and eager to recover lost
ground, were favourable to the success of List's book, and it produced a great sensation. He ably
represented the tendencies and demands of his time in his own country; his work had the effect of
fixing the attention, not merely of the speculative and official classes, but of practical men generally,
on questions of Political Economy; and he had without doubt an important influence on German
industrial policy. So far as science is concerned, the emphasis he laid on the relative historical study
of stages of civilization as affecting economic questions, and his protest against absolute formulas,
had a certain value; and the preponderance given to the national development over the immediate
gains of individuals was sound in principle; though his doctrine was, both on its public and private
sides, too much of a mere chrematistic, and tended in fact to set up a new form of mercantilism,
rather than to aid the contemporary effort towards social reform.
Most of the writers at home or abroad hitherto mentioned continued the traditions of the school of
Smith, only developing his doctrine in particular directions, sometimes not without one-sidedness or
exaggeration, or correcting minor errors into which he had fallen, or seeking to give to the exposition
of his principles more of order and lucidity. Some assailed the abuse of abstraction by Smith's
successors, objected to the conclusions of Ricardo and his followers their non-accordance with the
actual facts of human life, or protested against the anti-social consequences which seemed to result
from the application of the (so-called) orthodox formulas. A few challenged Smith's fundamental
ideas, and insisted on the necessity of altering the basis of general philosophy on which his
economics ultimately rest. But, notwithstanding various premonitory indications, nothing substantial,
at least nothing effective, was done, within the field we have as yet surveyed, towards the
establishment of a really new order of thinking, or new mode of proceeding, in this branch of inquiry.
Now, however, we have to describe a great and growing movement, which has already considerably
changed the whole character of the study in the conceptions of many, and which promises to
exercise a still more potent influence in the future. We mean the rise of the Historical School, which
we regard as marking the third epoch in the modern development of economic science.
Notes:
1. An English translation of the Dixme Royale was published in 1708.
2. "Richard Cantillon and the Nationality of Political Economy," in Contemporary Review, Jan. 1881.
Cantillon is quoted in the Wealth of Nations, bk. i. chap. 8.
3. Gournay strongly recommended to his friends Cantillon's book as "ouvrage excellent qu'on
négligeait." Mémoires de Morellet, i. 38.
4. See Cliffe Leslie's Essays in Political and Moral Philosophy. p. 151.
5. Prof. Ricca-Salemo (Le Dottrine Finanziarie in Inghilterra) has called attention to the fact that the
proposal of a single tax, on land, grounded on theoretic principles identical with those of the
Physiocrats, was put forward, and supported with much clearness and force, so early as 1714, by
Jacob Vanderlint. an Englishman, in his tract entitled Money answers all things.
6. A complete edition of the OEuvres économiques et philosophiques of Quesnay was published by
Oncken in 1888.
7. Wealth of Nations, bk. iv, chap. 9.
8. Ibid. bk. i, chap. 11.
9. Gournay's inspiration was, without doubt, largely English. "Il avait lu," says Morellet, "de bons
livres Anglais d'Économie politique, tells que Petty, Davennat, Gee, Child, etc." -- Mémoires, i. 18.
10. Other less prominent members of the group were Letrosni and the Abbé Baudeau.
11. On Galiani's Dialogues, see page 72. Soon after the appearance of this book Turgot wrote to
Mlle. de Lespinasse -- "Je crois possible de lui faire une très bonne réponse; mais cela demande
bien de l'art. Les économistes sont trop confiants pour combattre contre un si adroit ferrailleur. Pour
l'abbe Morellet, il ne faut pas qu'il y pense." Morellet's work was prohibited by the Controller-Général
Terray; though printed in 1770, some months after Galliani's, it was not published till 1774 -- Adam
Smith speaks of Morellet as "an eminent French author, of great knowledge in matters of political
economy" (Bk, v, chap, I).
12. Hume, in a letter to Morellet, 1769, calls them "the set of men the most chimerical and arrogant
that now exist." He seems intentionally to ignore Morellet's close connection with them.
13. Turgot said, "Quiconque n'oublie pas qu'il y a des états politiques séparés les uns des autres et
constitués diversement, ne traitera jamais bien aucune question d'Économie politique." Letter to
Mlle. des Lespinasse, 1770.
14. See also Grimm: "C'est Piaton avec la verve et les gestes d'Ariequin." Diderot called the book
"modèle de dialogues qui reatera à côté les lettres de Pascal."
15. J. S. Mill, in his Principles, bk. i. chap. I, takes credit to his father for having first illustrated and
made prominent in relation to production what he strangely calls, a fundamental principle of Political
Economy," namely, that "all that man does or can do with matter" is to "move one thing to or from
another." But the is clearly put foward by Verri in his Meditazioni, sect. 3: "Accostare e separare
sono gt uaici elementi che l'ingegno umano ritrova analizzando l'idea della riproduzione."
16. History of America, note 193
17. Philosophie Positive, vol. v p. 759.
18. Roschel, Geschichte der N.O. in Deutschland, p. 498.
19. An earlier work of P. de la Court, the Interese van Holland ofte Gronden van Hollands-Welvaren
(1662), was much read in the seventeenth century There is one English and three German
translations of this book.
20. Bk. v, chap. i, art. 3.
21. Smith says, in a letter to Pulteney (1772) -- "I have the same opinion of Sir James Steuart's book
that you have. Without once mentioning it, I flatter myself that any false principle in it will meet with a
clear and distinct confutation in mine."
22. "When I recollect what the President Montesquieu has written, I am at a loss to tell why I should
treat of human affairs; but I too am instigated by my reflections and my sentiments; and I may utter
them more to the comprehension of ordinary capacities, because I am more on the level of ordinary
men... the reader should be referred to what has been already delivered on the subject by this
profound politician and amiable moralist" (Part I, sect. 10). Hume speaks of Montesquieu as an
"illustrious writer," who "has established... a system of political knowledge, which abounds in
ingenious and brilliant thoughts and is not wanting in solidity" (Principles of Morals, sect. 3 and
note).
23. The following paragraph appeared in Moniteur Universel of March 11, 1790: -- "On prétend que
le célébre M. Smith, connu si avantageusement par son traité des causes de la richesse des
nations, prépare et va mettre l'impression un examen critique de 'Esprit des Lois; c'est le résultat de
pleusiers années de méditaion, et l'on sait assez ce qu'on a droit d'attendre d'une tête comme celle
de M. Smith. Ce livre fera époque dans l'histoire de la politique et de la philosophie, tel est du moins
le jugement qu'en portent des gens instruits qui en connaissent des fragments dont ils ne parient
qu'avec un enthousiasme du plus heureux augure."
24. Smith takes no account in this place of the evils which may arise from a highly developed
division of labour. But see Bk. v, chap. i.
25. This sentence, which on close examination will be found to have no definite intelligible sense,
affords a good example of the way in which metaphysical modes of thought obscure economic
ideas. What is a "quantity of labour," the kind of labour being undetermined? And what is meant by
the phrase "of equal value"?
26. Smith's expressions on this point are lax, as will be seen when we come to examine the (so-
called) Ricardian theory of Rent.
27. See p. 110, on Bentham.
28. It must, however, always be borne in mind that the adoption by a state of this sort of protection is
liable to three practical dangers: -- (1) of encouragement being procured through political influences
for industries which could never have an independent healthy life in the country -- (2) of such
encouragement being continued beyond the term during which it might be usefully given; (3) of a
retaliatory spirit of exclusion being provoked in other communities.
29. Professor Bastable calls the author's attention to the interesting fact that the proposal of an
export duty on wool and the justification of a temporary monopoly to joint-stock companies both
appear for the first time in the third edition (1784).
30. In the Introductory Essay to his edition of the Wealth of Nations.
31. "The public will probably soon be furnished with a theory of national economy, equal to what has
ever appeared on any subject of science whatever." (Part III, sect. 4).
32. Five editions of the Wealth of Nations appeared during the life of the author: -- the first in 1776,
The second in 1779, the third in 1784, the fourth in 1786, and the fifth in 1789. After the third edition
Smith made no change in the text. The principal editions containing matter added by other
economists are those by William Playfair, with notes, 1805; by David Buchanan, with notes, 1814;
by J. R. M'Culloch, with life of the author, introductory discourse, notes, and supplemental
dssertations, 1828 (also, with numerous additions, 1839; since reprinted several times with further
additions); by the author of England and America (Edward Gibbon Wakefield), with a commentary
which, however, is not continued beyond the second book, 1835-9; by James E. Thorold Rogers,
Professor of Political Economy at Oxford, with biographical preface and a useful verification of
Smith's quotation and references, 1869 (2d ed., 1880) -- and by J. S. Nicholson, professor at
Edinburgh, with an Introductory Essay, and notes referring to sources of further information on the
various topics handled in the text, 1884. There is a careful Abridgment by W P. Emerton (2d ed.,
1881), founded on the early Analysis Jeremiah Joyce (3d ed., 1821).
33. Parl. Hist., vol. xxxiii, p. 778.
34. It must be remembered, however, that the same doctrine had been supported with no less ability
as early as 1769 by Turgot in his Mémoire sur les prêts d'argent.
35. Lettres d'A. Comte à J. S. Mill, p. 4.
36. In his discourse at the Sorbonne (1760), Sur les progrès successifs de l'esprit humain.
37. Their dates are 1806, 1807, 1816, 1817, 1826.
38. On this subject see the speculations of Herbert Spencer in his Principle of Biology, Part VI,
chaps. xii, xiii.
39. Malthus himself said: -- "It is probable that, having found the bow bent too much one way, I was
induced to bend it too much the other in order to make it straight."
40. The Essay on Population and the Inquiry into the Nature and Progress of Rent (1815), to be
hereafter mentioned, are by far the most important contributions of Malthus to the science. He was
also author of Principles of Political Economy (1820). Definitions in Political Economy (1827), and
other minor pieces. On these less important writings of Malthus, and on his personal history, see
Malthus and his Work (1885), by James Bonar, who has also edited (1888) the Letters of Ricardo to
Malthus.
41. "Political economy, you think, is in inquiry into the nature and causes of wealth; I think it should
rather be called an inquiry into the laws that determine the division of the produce of industry
amongst the classes who concur in its formation." -- Letters of Ricardo to Malthus, ed. by J. Bonar
(1889).
42. Anderson's account of the origin of rent is reprinted in the Select Collection of Scarce and
Valuable Economical Tracts, edited for Lord Overstone by J. R. M'Culloch, 1859.
43. Senior, however, has pointed out that Smith is partly right; whilst it is true that rent is demanded
because the productive powers of nature are limited, and increased population requires a less
remunerative expenditure in order to obtain the necessary supply; on the other hand, it is the power
which most land possesses of producing the subsistance of more persons than art required for its
cultivation that supplies the fund out of which rent can be paid.
44. "As the colony increases, the profits of stock gradually diminish. When the most fertile and best
situated lands have been all occupied, less profit can be made by the cultivation of what is inferior
both in soil and situation, and less interest can be afforded for the stock which is so employed." The
view in question had been anticipated by West.
45. Adam Smith says: -- "It appears evidently from experience that man is, of all sorts of luggage,
the most difficult to be transported " (Wealth of Nations. Bk. I, chap. viii).
46. Tenant's Gain not Landlord's Loss (1883), p. 83.
47. Zwei Bücher zur Socialen Geschichte Englands, p. 194.
48. A sketch of Ricardo's personal history, and an account of his writings on monetary questions,
which could not conveniently be introduced here will be found under his name in the Encyclopaedia
Britannica, 9th edition.
49. Thus, in Wealth of Nations, Bk. I, chap. vii, we have the phrase "the funds which are destined to
the payment of wages," " the funds destined for employing industry " "the funds destined for the
maintenance of servants "
50. See the last of his Four Introductory Lectures on Political; Economy, 1852.
51. Mill, however, tells us in his Preface to those Essays that his own views on that subject had
been entertained and committed to writing before the publication by Torrens of similar opinions.
52. Samuel Crumpe, M.D., had published at Dublin in 1793 an Essay on the Best Means of
Providing Employment for the People, which obtained a prize offered by the Royal Irish Academy for
the best dissertation on that subject. This is a meritorious work, and contains a good statement of
some of the leading principles of Adam Smith. John Hely Hutchinson's Commercial Restraints of
Ireland (1779) is important for the economic history of that country.
53. Afterwards Lord Ashburton. For this Petition, see M'Culloch's Literature of Political Economy, p.
57, or Senior's Lectures on the Transmission of the Precious Metals, etc., 2d ed., p. 78.
54. Curiously, in an otherwise well-executed abridgment of Mill's work published in the United
States (1886) by J. Laurence Laughlin, as a textbook tor colleges, all that "should properly be
classed under the head of Sociology " has been omitted, Mill's own conception being thus set aside,
and his book made to conform to the common type.
55. Mr John Morley ("Mill on Religion", in Critical Miscellanies, 2d ser, 1877) betrays something
consternation at finding in Mill's posthumous writings statements of opinion distinctly at variance
with philosophic doctrines he had energetically maintained during his whole life.
56. See also his Chapters on Socialism, in Fortnightly Review, 1879
57. Economists are fond of comparing the rate of profit or wages in one nation (using this word in its
economic sense) to a single fluid surface which is continually disturbed by transient influences and
continually tending to recover its level. We must compare these rates in different nations to
reservoirs which, not communicating with each other, stand always at different, though variable,
levels. And the latter comparison will apply also to the rates (al least of wages) in different economic
"groups", or strata, within the same community.
58. See p. 139.
59. Jevons strangely says, in the Preface to his Theory of Political Economy, 2d. ed., that the wages
fund doctrine " has been abandoned by most English economists owing to the attacks," amongst
others. "Of Cairnes." Cairnes was, in truth, a supporter of the doctrine.
60. In his Essay on the Principle of Commercial Exchanges.
61. On this whole subject see Professor C.F. Bastable's Theory of International Trade, 1887.
62. The first French translation of the Wealth of Nations, by Blavet, appeared in the Journal de
l'Agriculture, du Commerce, des Finances, et des Arts, 1779-80; new editions of it were published in
1781, 1788,and 1800; it was also printed at Amsterdam in 1784. Smith himself recommended it in
his third edition of the original as excellent. In 1790 appeared the translation by Roucher, to which
Condorcet had intended to add notes, and in 1802 that by Count Germain Garnier, executed during
his exile in England which is now considered the standard version, and has been reproduced, with
notes by Say, Sismondi, Blanqui, etc., in the Collection des Prinicipaux Economistes.
63. He grossly exaggerated Smith's faults of method. Thus he saysL'ouvrage de Smith n'est qu'un
assemblage confus des principes les plus sains de l'Economie politique . . . son livre est un vaste
chaos d'idées justes - (Discours Préliminaire).
64. The French economists are continued on page 175.
65. Hamilton's Works, edited by H. C. Lodge, vol. iii, p; 294.
66. It is, however, a mistake to suppose that the assumption of this historical order of descent is
essential to the theory in question.
67. This argument seems scarcely met by Professor F. A. Walker, Political Economy, 5052. But
perhaps he is right in thinking that Carey exaggerates the importance of the considerations on which
it is founded. Mill and Leslie remark that the transportation of agricultural products from the western
to the Atlantic States has the same effect as their export to Europe, so far as this so-called "land-
butchery" is concerned; besides some manures are obtainable from abroad.
68. Other writings of Carey's besides his Social Science are his Essay on the Rate of Wages
(1835); Principles of Political Economy (18381840) Past, Present, and Future (1848) Unity of Law
(1872).
69. Charles Comte (17821837) was son-in-law of J. B. Say. He was associated with Dunoyer in his
political writings and, like him, distinguished for his honourable independence. He was author of the
Traité de Législation, a meritorious and useful, but not a profound work.
70. M. Leroy-Beaulieu maintains (Essai sur la Répartition des Richesses, 2d ed., 1882) that this,
though not strictly, is approximately truethat economic forms a very small part of actual rent.
71. Essays in Political Economy, p. 334.
72. Hermann Heinrich Gossen's work, Entwickelung der Gesetze des nutsschlichan Verkehrs, so
highly praised by Jevons, Theory of Pol. Econ., 2d ed., Pref., was published in 1854.
73. The first German version of the Wealth of Nations was that by Johann Friedrich Schiller,
published 177678. The second, which is the first good one, was by Chnstian Garve and again 1799
and 1810). A later one by C. W. Asher (1861) is highly commended.
CHAPTER VI
THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL
The negative movement which filled the eighteenth century had for its watchword on the economic
side the liberation of industrial effort from both feudal survivals and Governmental fetters. But in all
the aspects of that movement, the economic as well as the rest, the process of demolition was
historically only the necessary preliminary condition of a total renovation towards which Western
Europe was energetically tending, though with but an indistinct conception of its precise nature. The
disorganization of the body of opinion which underlay the old system outran the progress towards
the establishment of new principles adequate to form a guidance in the future. The critical
philosophy which had wrought the disorganization could only repeat its formulas of absolute liberty,
but was powerless for reconstruction. And hence there was seen throughout the West, after the
French explosion, the remarkable spectacle of a continuous oscillation between the tendency to
recur to outworn ideas and a vague impulse towards a new order in social thought and life, this
impulse often taking an anarchical character.
From this state of oscillation, which has given to the 19th century its equivocal and transitional
aspect, the only possible issue was in the foundation of a scientific social doctrine which should
supply a basis for the gradual convergence of opinion on human questions. The foundation of such
a doctrine is the immortal service for which the world is indebted to Auguste Comte (17981857).
The leading features of Sociology, as he conceived it, are the following:(1) it is essentially one
science, in which all the elements of a social state are studied in their relations and mutual actions;
(2) it includes a dynamical as well as a statical theory of society; (3) it thus eliminates the absolute,
substituting for an imagined fixity the conception of ordered change; (4) its principal method, though
others are not excluded, is that of historical comparison; (5) it is pervaded by moral ideas, by notions
of social duty, as opposed to the individual rights which were derived as corollaries from the jus
naturae; and (6) in its spirit and practical consequences it tends to the realisation of all the great
ends which compose "the popular cause" ; yet (7) it aims at this through peaceful means, replacing
revolution by evolution.(1) The several characteristics we have enumerated are not independent;
they may be shown to be vitally connected with each other. Several of these features must now be
more fully described; the others will meet us before the close of the present survey.
In the masterly exposition of sociological method which is contained in the fourth volume of the
Philosophie Positive (1839),(2) Comte marks out the broad division between social statics and
social dynamicsthe former studying the laws of social coexistence, the latter those of social
development. The fundamental principle of the former is the general consensus between the several
social organs and functions, which, without unduly pressing a useful analogy, we may regard as
resembling that which exists between the several organs and functions of an animal body. The
study of dynamical is different from, and necessarily subordinated to, that of statical sociology,
progress being in fact the development of order, just as the study of evolution in biology is different
from, and subordinated to, that of the structures and functions which are exhibited by evolution as
they exist at the several points of an ascending scale. The laws of social coexistence and
movement are as much subjects for observation as the corresponding phenomena in the life of an
individual organism. For the study of development in particular, a modification of the comparative
method familiar to biologists will be the appropriate mode of research. The several successive
stages of society will have to be systematically compared, in order to discover their laws of
sequence, and to determine the filiation of their characteristic features.
Though we must take care that both in our statical and dynamical studies we do not ignore or
contradict the fundamental properties of human nature, the project of deducing either species of
laws from those properties independently of direct observation is one which cannot be realised.
Neither the general structure of human society nor the march of its development could be so
predicted. This is especially evident with respect to dynamical laws, because, in the passage of
society from one phase to another, the preponderating agency is the accumulated influence of past
generations, which is much too complex to be investigated deductivelya conclusion which it is
important to keep steadily before us now that some of the (so-called) anthropologists are seeking to
make the science of society a mere annex and derivative of biology. The principles of biology
unquestionably lie at the foundation of the social science, but the latter has, and must always have,
a field of research and a method of inquiry peculiar to itself. The field is history in the largest sense,
including contemporary fact; and the principal, though not exclusive, method is, as we have said,
that process of sociological comparison which is most conveniently called "the historical method."
These general principles affect the economic no less than other branches of social speculation; and
with respect to that department of inquiry they lead to important results. They show that the idea of
forming a true theory of the economic frame and working of society apart from its other sides is
illusory. Such study is indeed provisionally indispensable, but no rational theory of the economic
organs and functions of society can be constructed if they are considered as isolated from the rest.
In other words, a separate economic science is, strictly speaking, an impossibility, as representing
only one portion of a complex organism, all whose parts and their actions are in a constant relation
of correspondence and reciprocal modification. Hence, too, it will follow that, whatever useful
indications may be derived from our general knowledge of individual human nature, the economic
structure of society and its mode of development cannot be deductively foreseen, but must be
ascertained by direct historical investigation. We have said "its mode of development " ; for it is
obvious that, as of every social element, so of the economic factor in human affairs, there must be a
dynamical doctrine, a theory of the successive phases of the economic condition of society yet in
the accepted systems this was a desideratum, nothing but some partial and fragmentary notions on
this whole side of the subject being yet extant.(3) And, further, the economic structure and working
of one historic stage being different from those of another, we must abandon the idea of an absolute
system possessing universal validity, and substitute that of a series of such systems, in which,
however, the succession is not at all arbitrary, but is itself regulated by law.
Though Comte's enterprise was a constructive one, his aim being the foundation of a scientific
theory of society, he could not avoid criticising the labours of those who before him had treated
several branches of social inquiry. Amongst them the economists were necessarily considered; and
he urged or implied, in various places of his above-named work, as well as of his Politique Positive,
objections to their general ideas and methods of procedure essentially the same with those which
we stated in speaking of Ricardo and his followers. J. S. Mill shows himself much irritated by these
comments, and remarks on them as showing" how extremely superficial M. Comte" (whom he yet
regards as a thinker quite comparable with Descartes and Leibnitz) "could sometimes be,"an
unfortunate observation, which he would scarcely have made if he could have foreseen the
subsequent march of European thought, and the large degree in which the main points of Comte's
criticism have been accepted or independently reproduced.
GERMANY
The second manifestation of this new movement in economic science was the appearance of the
German historical school. The views of this school do not appear to have arisen, like Comte's theory
of sociological method, out of general philosophic ideas; they seem rather to have been suggested
by an extension to the economic field of the conceptions of the historical school of jurisprudence of
which Savigny was the most eminent representative. The juristic system is not a fixed social
phenomenon, but is variable from one stage in the progress of society to another; it is in vital
relation with the other coexistent social factors; and what is, in the jural sphere, adapted to one
period of development, is often unfit for another. These ideas were seen to be applicable to the
economic system also; the relative point of view was thus reached, and the absolute attitude was
found to be untenable. Cosmopolitanism in theory, or the assumption of a system equally true of
every country, and what has been called perpetualism, or the assumption of a system applicable to
every social stage, were alike discredited. And so the German historical school appears to have
taken its rise.
Omitting preparatory indications and undeveloped germs of doctrine, we must trace the origin of the
school to Wilhelm Roscher (18171894). Its fundamental principles are stated, though with some
hesitation, and with an unfortunate contrast of the historical with the" philosophical "method,(4) in his
Grundriss zu Vorlesungen über die Staatswirthschaft nach geschichtlicher Methode (1843). The
following are the leading heads insisted on in the preface to that work.
"The historical method exhibits itself not merely in the external form of a treatment of phenomena
according to their chronological succession, but in the following fundamental ideas. (1.) The aim is
to represent what nations have thought, willed, and discovered in the economic field, what they have
striven after and attained, and why they have attained it. (2.) A people is not merely the mass of
individuals now living; it will not suffice to observe contemporary facts. (3.) All the peoples of whom
we can learn anything must be studied and compared from the economic point of view, especially
the ancient peoples, whose development lies before us in its totality. (4.) We must not simply praise
or blame economic institutions; few of them have been salutary or detrimental to all peoples and at
all stages of culture; rather it is a principal task of science to show how and why, out of what was
once reasonable and beneficent, the unwise and inexpedient has often gradually arisen." Of the
principles enunciated in this paraphrase of Roscher's words a portion of the third alone seems open
to objection; the economy of ancient peoples is not a more important subject of study than that of
the moderns; indeed, the question of the relative importance of the two is one that ought not to be
raised. For the essential condition of all sound sociological inquiry is the comparative consideration
of the entire series of the most complete evolution known to historythat, namely, of the group of
nations forming what is known as the Occidental Commonwealth, or, more briefly, " the West." The
reasonsfor choosing this social series, and for provisionally restricting our studies almost altogether
to it, have been stated with unanswerable force by Comte in the Philosophie Positive. Greece and
Rome are, indeed, elements in the series; but it is the development as a whole, not any special
portions of it, that Sociology must keep in view in order to determine the laws of the movement,just
as, in the study of biological evolution, no one stage of an organism can be considered as of
preponderating importance, the entire succession of changes being the object of research. Of
Roscher's further eminent services we shall speak hereafter; he is now mentioned only in relation to
the origin of the new school.
In 1848 Bruno Hildebrand (18121878) published the first volume of a work, which, though he lived
for many years after, he never continued, entitled Die Nationalökonomie der Gegenwart und
Zukunft. Hildebrand was a thinker of a really high order; it may be doubted whether amongst
German economists there has been any endowed with a more profound and searching intellect. He
is quite free from the wordiness and obscurity which too often characterise German writers, and
traces broad outlines with a sure and powerful hand. His book contains a masterly criticism of the
economic systems which preceded, or belonged to, his time, including those of Smith, Muller, List,
and the socialists. But it is interesting to us at present mainly from the general position he takes up,
and his conception of the real nature of political economy. The object of his work, he tells us, is to
open a way in the economic domain to a thorough historical direction and method, and to transform
the science into a doctrine of the laws of the economic development of nations. It is interesting to
observe that the type which he sets before him in his proposed reform of political economy is not
that of historical jurisprudence, but of the science of language as it has been reconstructed in the
i9th century, a selection which indicates the comparative method as the one which he considered
appropriate. In both sciences we have the presence of an ordered variation in time, and the
consequent substitution of the relative for the absolute.
In 1853 appeared the work of Karl Knies (18211898), entitled Die Politische Oekonomie von
Standpunkte der geschichtlichen Methode. This is an elaborate exposition and defence of the
historical method in its application to economic science, and is the most systematic and complete
manifesto of the new school, at least on the logical side. The fundamental propositions are that the
economic constitution of society at any epoch on the one hand, and on the other the contemporary
theoretic conception of economic science, are results of a definite historical development; that they
are both in vital connection with the whole social organism of the period, having grown up along with
it and under the same conditions of time, place, and nationality; that the economic system must
therefore be regarded as passing through a series of phases correlative with the successive stages
of civilization, and can at no point of this movement be considered to have attained an entirely
definitive form; that no more the present than any previous economic organization of society is to be
regarded as absolutely good and right, but only as a phase in a continuous historical evolution; and
that in like manner the now prevalent economic doctrine is not to be viewed as complete and final,
but only as representing a certain stage in the unfolding or progressive manifestation of the truth.
The theme of the book is handled with, perhaps, an undue degree of expansion and detail. The
author exhibits much sagacity as well as learning, and criticises effectively the errors,
inconsistencies, and exaggerations of his predecessors. But in characterising and vindicating the
historical method he has added nothing to Comte. A second edition of his treatise was published in
1883, and in this he makes the singular confession that, when he wrote in 1852, the Philosophie
Positive, the six volumes of which had appeared from 1830 to 1842, was entirely unknown to him
and, he adds, probably to all German economists. This is not to the credit of their open-mindedness
or literary vigilance, if we remember that Mill was already in correspondence with Comte in 1841,
and that his eulogistic notice of him in the Logic appeared in 1843. When, however, Knies at a later
period examined Comte's work, he was, he tells us, surprised at finding in it so many anticipations
of, or "parallelisms" with, his own conclusions. And well he might; for all that is really valuable in his
methodology is to be found in Comte, applied on a larger scale, and designed with the broad and
commanding power which marks the dii majores of philosophy.
There are two points which seem to be open to criticism in the position taken by some German
economists of the historical school.
1. Knies and some other writers, in maintaining the principle of relativity in economic theory, appear
not to preserve the due balance in one particular. The two forms of absolutism in doctrine,
cosmopolitanism and what Knies calls perpetualism, he seems to place on exactly the same footing;
in other words, he considers the error of overlooking varieties of local circumstances and nationality
to be quite as serious as that of neglecting differences in the stage of historical development. But
this is certainly not so. In every branch of Sociology the latter is much the graver error, vitiating
radically, wherever it is found, the whole of our investigations. If we ignore the fact, or mistake the
direction, of the social movement, we are wrong in the most fundamental point of alla point, too,
which is involved in every question. But the variations depending on difference of race, as affecting
bodily and mental endowment, or on diversity of external situation, are secondary phenomena only;
they must be postponed in studying the general theory of social development, and taken into
account afterwards when we come to examine the modifications in the character of the development
arising out of peculiar conditions. And, though the physical nature of a territory is a condition which
is likely to operate with special force on economic phenomena, it is rather on the technical forms
and comparative extension of the several branches of industry that it will act than on the social
conduct of each branch, or the co-ordination and relative action of all, which latter are the proper
subjects of the inquiries of the economist.
2. Some members of the school appear, in their anxiety to assert the relativity of the science, to fall
into the error of denying economic laws altogether; they are at least unwilling to speak of "natural
laws" in relation to the economic world. From a too exclusive consideration of law in the inorganic
sphere, they regard this phraseology as binding them to the notion of fixity and of an invariable
system of practical economy. But, if we turn our attention rather to the organic sciences, which are
more kindred to the social, we shall see that the term "natural law" carries with it no such
implication. As we have more than once indicated, an essential part of the idea of life is that of
development, in other words, of "ordered change." And that such a development takes place in the
constitution and working of society in all its elements is a fact which cannot be doubted, and which
these writers themselves, emphatically assert. That there exist between the several social elements
such relations as make the change of one element involve or determine the change of another is
equally plain; and why the name of natural laws should be denied to such constant relations of
coexistence and succession it is not easy to see. These laws, being universal, admit of the
construction of an abstract theory of economic development; whilst a part of the German historical
school tends to substitute for such a theory a mere description of different national economies,
introducing prematurelyas we have pointed outthe action of special territorial or ethnological
conditions, instead of reserving this as the ground of later modifications, in concrete cases, of the
primary general laws deduced from a study of the common human evolution.
To the three writers above named, Roscher, Hildebrand, and Knies, the foundation of the German
historical school of political economy belongs. It does not appear that Roscher in his own
subsequent labours has been much under the influence of the method which he has in so many
places admirably characterised. In his System der Volkswirthschaft (vol. i., Grundlagen der
Nationaleökonomie, 1854; 23rd ed., 1900; Eng. transi. by J. J. Lalor, 1878; vol. ii., N. O. des
Ackerbaues, 1860; 13th ed., 1903; vol. iii., N. O. des Handels und Gewerbfleisses, 7th ed., 1887)
the dogmatic and the historical matter are rather juxtaposed than vitally combined. It is true that he
has most usefully applied his vast learning to special historical studies, in relation especially to the
progress of the science itself. His treatise Ueber das Verhdltniss der Nationalökonomie zum
classischen Alterthume (1849), his Zur Geschichte der Englischen Voikswirthschaftslehre (18512),
and, above all, that marvellous monument of erudition and industry, his Gesehichie der National-
Oekonomik in Deutschland (1874), to which he is said to have devoted fifteen years of study, are
among the most valuable extant works of this kind, though the last by its accumulation of detail is
unfitted for general study outside of Germany itself. Several interesting and useful monographs are
collected in his Ansichten der Volkswirthschaft vom geschichtlichen Standpunkte (1861, 3d ed.,
1878). His systematic treatise, too, above referred to, abounds in historical notices of the rise and
development of the several doctrines of the science. But it cannot be alleged that he has done much
towards the transformation of political economy which his earliest labours seemed to announce; and
Cossa appears to be right in saying that his dogmatic work has not effected any substantial
modification of the principles of Hermann and Rau.
The historical method has exhibited its essential features more fully in the hands of the younger
generation of scientific economists in Germany, amongst whom may be reckoned Lujo Brentano,
Adolf Held, Erwin Nasse, Gustav Schmoller, H. Rösler, Albert Schäffle, Hans von Scheel, Gustav
Schönberg, and Adolf Wagner. Besides the general principle of an historical treatment of the
science, the leading ideas which have been most strongly insisted on by this school are the
following. I. The necessity of accentuating the moral element in economic study. This consideration
has been urged with special emphasis by Schmoller in his Grundiragen der Rechtes und der Moral
(1875) and by Schäffle in his Das gesellschaftliche System der menschlichen Wirthschaft (1861, 3d
ed., 1873). G. Kries (d. 1858) appears also to have handled the subject well in a review of J. S. Mill.
According to the most advanced organs of the school, three principles of organization are at work in
practical economy; and, corresponding with these, there are three different systems or spheres of
activity. The latter are (1) private economy; (2) the compulsory public economy; (3) the "caritative"
sphere. In the first alone personal interest predominates; in the second the general interest of the
society; in the third the benevolent impulses. Even in the first, however, the action of private
interests cannot be unlimited; not to speak here of the intervention of the public power, the excesses
and abuses of the fundamental principle in this department must be checked and controlled by an
economic morality, which can never be left out of account in theory any more than in practical
applications. In the third region above named, moral influences are of course supreme. II. The close
relation which necessarily exists between economics and jurisprudence. This has been brought out
by L. von Stein and H. Rösler, but is most systematically established by Wagnerwho is, without
doubt, one of the most eminent of living German economistsespecially in his Grundlegung, now
forming part of the comprehensive Lehrbuch der politischen Oekonomie published by him and
Professor Nasse jointly. The doctrine of the jus nature, on which the physiocrats, as we have seen,
reared their economic structure, has lost its hold on belief, and the old a priori and absolute
conceptions of personal freedom and property have given way along with it. It is seen that the
economic position of the individual, instead of depending merely on so-called natural rights or even
on his natural powers, is conditioned by the contemporary juristic system, which is itself an historical
product. The above-named conceptions, therefore, half economic half juristic, of freedom and
property require a fresh examination. It is principally from this point of view that Wagner approaches
economic studies. The point, as he says, on which all turns is the old question of the relation of the
individual to the community. Whoever with the older juristic and political philosophy and national
economy places the individual in the centre comes necessarily to the untenable results which, in the
economic field, the physiocratic and Smithian school of free competition has set up. Wagner on the
contrary investigates, before anything else, the conditions of the economic life of the community,
and, in subordination to this, determines the sphere of the economic freedom of the individual. III. A
different conception of the functions of the State from that entertained by the school of Smith. The
latter school has in general followed the view of Rousseau and Kant that the sole office of the state
is the protection of the members of the community from violence and fraud. This doctrine, which
was in harmony with those of the jus naturae and the social contract, was temporarily useful for the
demolition of the old economic system with its complicated apparatus of fetters and restrictions. But
it could not stand against a rational historical criticism, and still less against the growing practical
demands of modern civilization. In fact, the abolition of the impolitic and discredited system of
European Governments, by bringing to the surface the evils arising from unlimited competition,
irresistibly demonstrated the necessity of public action according to new and more enlightened
methods. The German historical school recognizes the State as not merely an institution for the
maintenance of order, but as the organ of the nation for all ends which cannot be adequately
effected by voluntary individual effort. Whenever social aims can be attained only or most
advantageously through its action, that action is justified.(5) The cases in which it can properly
interfere must be determined separately on their own merits and in relation to the stage of national
development. It ought certainly to promote intellectual and aesthetic culture. It ought to enforce
provisions for public health and regulations for the proper conduct of production and transport. It
ought to protect the weaker members of society, especially women, children, the aged, and the
destitute, at least in the absence of family maintenance and guardianship. It ought to secure the
labourer against the worst consequences of personal injury not due to his own negligence, to assist
through legal recognition and supervision the efforts of the working classes for joint no less than
individual self-help, and to guarantee the safety of their earnings, when intrusted to its care.
A special influence which has worked on this more recent group is that of theoretic socialism; we
shall see hereafter that socialism as a party organization has also affected their practical politics.
With such writers as St. Simon, Fourier, and Proudhon, Lassalle, Marx, Engels, Marlo, and
Rodhertus, we do not deal in the present treatise; but we must recognize them as having powerfully
stimulated the younger German economists (in the more limited sense of this last word). They have
even modified the scientific conclusions of the latter, principally through criticism of the so-called
orthodox system. Schäffle and Wagner may be especially named as having given a large space and
a respectful attention to their arguments. In particular, the important consideration, to which we have
already referred, that the economic position of the individual depends on the existing legal system,
and notably on the existing organization of property, was first insisted on by the socialists. They had
also pointed out that the present institutions of society in relation to property, inheritance, contract,
and the like, are (to use Lassalle's phrase) "historical categories which have changed, and are
subject to further change," whilst in the orthodox economy they are generally assumed as a fixed
order of things on the basis of which the individual creates his own position. J. S. Mill, as we have
seen, called attention to the fact of the distribution of wealth depending, unlike its production, not on
natural laws alone, but on the ordinances of society, but it is some of the German economists of the
younger historical school who have most strongly emphasised this view. To rectify and complete the
conception, however, we must bear in mind that those ordinances themselves are not arbitrarily
changeable, but are conditioned by the stage of general social development.
In economic politics these writers have taken up a position between the German free-trade (or, as it
is sometimes with questionable propriety called, the Manchester) party and the democratic
socialists. The latter invoke the omnipotence of the State to transform radically and immediately the
present economic constitution of society in the interest of the proletariate. The free-traders seek to
minimise state action for any end except that of maintaining public order, and securing the safety
and freedom of the individual. The members of the school of which we are now speaking, when
intervening in the discussion of practical questions, have occupied an intermediate standpoint. They
are opposed alike to social revolution and to rigid laisser faire. Whilst rejecting the socialistic
programme, they call for the intervention of the State in accordance with the theoretic principles
already mentioned, for the purpose of mitigating the pressure of the modern industrial system on its
weaker members, and extending in greater measure to the working classes the benefits of
advancing civilization. Schäffle in his Capitalismus und Socialismus (1870; now absorbed into a
larger work), Wagner in his Rede über die sociale Frage (1871), and Schanberg in his Arbeitsämter:
eine Aulgabe des deutschen Reichs (1871) advocated this policy in relation to the question of the
labourer. These expressions of opinion, with which most of the German professors of political
economy sympathised, were violently assailed by the organs of the free-trade party, who found in
them "a new form of socialism." Out of this arose a lively controversy; and the necessity of a closer
union and a practical political organization being felt amongst the partisans of the new direction, a
congress was held at Eisenach in October 1872, for the consideration of "the social question." It was
attended by almost all the professors of economic science in the German universities, by
representatives of the several political parties, by leaders of the working men, and by some of the
large capitalists. At this meeting the principles above explained were formulated. Those who
adopted them obtained from their opponents the appellation of "Katheder-Socialisten," or socialists
of the (professorial) chair," a nickname invented by H. B. Oppenheim, and which those to whom it
was applied were not unwilling to accept. Since 1873 this group has been united in the "Verein für
Social-politik," in which, as the controversy became mitigated, free-traders also have taken part.
Within the Verein a division has shown itself. The left wing has favoured a systematic gradual
modification of the law of property in such a direction as would tend to the fulfilment of the socialistic
aspirations, so far as these are legitimate, whilst the majority advocate reform through state action
on the basis of existing jural institutions. Schäffle goes so far as to maintain that the present
"capitalistic" regime will be replaced by a socialistic organization; but, like J. S. Mill, he adjourns this
change to a more or less remote future, and expects it as the result of a natural development, or
process of "social selection;"(6) he repudiates any immediate or violent revolution, and rejects any
system of life which would set up "abstract equality" against the claims of individual service and
merit.
The further the investigations of the German historical school have been carried, in the several lines
of inquiry it has opened, the more clearly it has come to light that the one thing needful is not merely
a reform of political economy, but its fusion in a complete science of society. This is the view long
since insisted on by Auguste Comte; and its justness is daily becoming more apparent. The best
economists of Germany now tend strongly in this direction. Schäffle (18311903), who was largely
under the influence of Comte and Herbert Spencer, actually attempted the enterprise of widening
economic into social studies. In his most important work, which had been prepared by previous
publications, Bau und Leben des socialen Körpers (187578; new ed., 1896), he proposes to give a
comprehensive plan
an anatomy, physiology, and psychology of human society. He considers social processes as
analogous to those of organic bodies; and, sound and suggestive as the idea of this analogy,
already used by Comte, undoubtedly is, he carries it, perhaps, to an undue degree of detail and
elaboration. The same conception is adopted, and presented in a very exaggerated form, by P. von
Lilienfeld in his Gedanken über die Socialzeissenschaft der Zukunft (187381). A tendency to the
fusion of economic science in Sociology is also found in Adolph Samter's Sozial-lehre (1875)though
the economic aspect of society is there specially studiedand in Schmoller's already mentioned
treatise Ueber einige Grundfragen; and the necessity of such a transformation is energetically
asserted by H. von Scheel in the preface to his German version (1879) of an English tract(7) On the
present Position and Prospects of Political Economy.
The name " Realistic," which has sometimes been given to the historical school, especially in its
more recent form, appears to be injudiciously chosen. It is intended to mark the contrast with the"
abstract "complexion of the orthodox economics. But the error of these economics lies, not in the
use, but in the abuse of abstraction. All science implies abstraction, seeking, as it does, for unity in
variety; the question in every branch is as to the right constitution of tlle abstract theory in relation to
the concrete facts. Nor is the new school quite correctly distinguished as "inductive." Deduction
doubtless unduly preponderates in the investigations of the older economists; but it must be
remembered that it is a legitimate process, when it sets out, not from a priori assumptions, but from
proved generalisations. And the appropriate method of economics, as of all sociology, is not so
much induction as the specialised form of induction known as comparison, especially the
comparative study of " social series " (to use Mill's phrase), which is properly designated as the
"historical" method. If the denominations here criticised were allowed to prevail, there would be a
danger of the school assuming an unscientific character. It might occupy itself too exclusively with
statistical inquiry, and forget in the detailed examination of particular provinces of economic life the
necessity of large philosophic ideas and of a systematic co-ordination of principles. So long as
economics remain a separate branch of study, and until they are absorbed into Sociology, the
thinkers who follow the new direction will do wisely in retaining their original designation of the
historical school.
The members of this and the other German schools have produced many valuable works besides
those which there has been occasion to mention above. Ample notices of their contributions to the
several branches of the science (including its applications) will be found dispersed through Wagner
and Nasse's Lehrbuch and the comprehensive Handbuch edited by Schönberg. The following list,
which does not pretend to approach to completeness, is given for the purpose of directing the
student to a certain number of books which ought not to be overlooked in the study of the subjects
to which they respectively refer:--
Knies, Die Eisenbahnen und ihre Wirkungen (1853), Der Telegraph (1857), Geld und Credit
(18737679); Rösler, Zur Kritik der Lekre vom Arbeitslohn (1861) ; Schmoller, Zur Geschichte aer
deutschen Klein gewerbe im 19 Jahrh. (1870) ; Schäffle, Theorie der ausschliessenden
Absatzverhaltnisse (1867), Quintessenz des socialismus (6th ed., 1878), Grundsatze der
Steuerpolitik (1880) Nasse, Mittelalterliche Feldgemeinschaft in England (1869); Brentano, On the
History and Development of Gilds, prefixed to Toulmin Smith's English Gilds (1870), Die
Arbeitergilden der Gegenwart (187172), Das Arbeitsverhaltniss gemass dem heutigen Recht (1877),
Die Arbeitsversicherung getnass der heutigen Wirthschaftsordnung (1879), Der
Arbeitsversicherungszwang (1884), Die klassische Nationalokonomie (1888); Held (born 1844,
accidentally drowned in the Lake of Thun, 1880), Die Einkommensteuer (1872), Die deutsche
Arbeiterpresse der Gegenwart (1873), Sozialismus, Sozialdemokratie und Sozialpolitik (1878),
Grundriss fur Vorlesungen uber Nationalokonomie (2d ed., 1878); Zwei Bucher zur socialen
Geschichte Englands (posthumously published, 1881); Von Scheel (born 1839), Die Theorie der
socialen Frage (1871), Unsere social politischen Parteien (1878); Von Böhm Bawerk, Kapital und
Kapitalzinstheorien (188489). To these may be added L. von Stein, Die Verwaltungslehre (187679),
Lehrbuch der Finanzwissenschaft (4th ed., 1878). E. Duhring is the ablest of the few German
followers of Carey; we have already mentioned (Bibl. Note) his History of the Science. To the
Russian German school belongs the work of T. von Bernhardi, which is written from the historical
point of view, Versuch einer Kritik der Grunde welehe fur grosses und kleines Grundeigenthum
angefuhrt werden (1848). The free trade school of Germany is recognized as having rendered great
practical services in that country, especially by its systematic warfare against antiquated privileges
and restrictions. Cobden has furnished the model of its political action, whilst, on the side of theory,
it is founded chiefly on Say and Bastiat. The members of this school whose names have been most
frequently heard by the English public are those of J. Prince Smith (d. 1874), who may be regarded
as having been its head; H. von Treitschke, author of Der Socialismus und seine Gonner, 1875
(directed against the Katheder Socialisten) V. Böhmert, who has advocated the participation of
workmen in profits (Die Gewinnbetheiligung, 1878); A. Emminghaus, author of Das Armenwesen in
Europaischen Staaten, 1870, part of which has been translated in E. B. Eastwick's Poor Relief in
Different Parts of Europe, 1873; and J. H. Schultze Delitzsch, well known as the founder of the
German popular banks, and a strenuous supporter of the system of "co-operation." The socialist
writers, as has been already mentioned, are not included in the present historical survey, nor do we
in general notice writings of the economists (properly so called) having relation to the history of
socialism or the controversy with it.
The movement which created the new school in Germany, with the developments which have grown
out of it, have without doubt given to that country at the present time the primacy in economic
studies. German influence has been felt in the modification of opinion in other countriesmost
strongly, perhaps, in Italy, and least so in France. In England it has been steadily making way,
though retarded by the insular indifference to the currents of foreign thought which has eminently
marked our dominant school. Alongside of the influence thus exerted, a general distaste for the
"orthodox" system has been spontaneously growing, partly from a suspicion that its method was
unsound, partly from a profound dissatisfaction with the practice it inspired, and the detected
hollowness of the policy of mere laisser faire. Hence everywhere a mode of thinking and a species
of research have shown themselves, and come into favour, which are in harmony with the
systematic conceptions of the historical economists. Thus a dualism has established itself in the
economic world, a younger school advancing towards predominance, whilst the old school still
defends its position, though its adherents tend more and more to modify their attitude and to admit
the value of the new lights.
ITALY
It is to be regretted that but little is known in England and America of the writings of the recent Italian
economists. Luigi Cossa's Guida, which was translated at the suggestion of Jevons,(8) has given us
some notion of the character and importance of their labours. The urgency of questions of finance in
Italy since its political renascence has turned their researches for the most part into practical
channels, and they have produced numerous monographs on statistical and administrative
questions. But they have also dealt ably with the general doctrines of the science. Cossa
pronounces Angelo Messedaglia (b. 1820), professor at Padna, to be the foremost of the Italian
economists of his time; he has written on public loans (1850) and on population (i858), and is
regarded as a master of the subjects of money and credit. His pupil Fedele Lampertico (b. 1833) is
author of many writings, among which the most systematic and complete is his Economia dei popoli
e degli stati (18741884). Marco Miughetti (18181886), distinguished as a minister, was author,
besides other writings, of Economza pubblica e le sue attinenze colla morale e col diritto (1859).
Luigi Luzzatti, also known as an able administrator, has by several publications sought to prepare
the way for reforms. The Sicilians Vito Cusumano and Giuseppe Ricca Salerno have produced
excellent works:the former on the history of political economy in the Middle Ages (1876), and on the
economic schools of Germany in their relation to the social question (1875) ; the latter on the
theories of capital, wages, and public loans (187789). G. Toniolo, E. Nazzani,(9) and A. Loria have
also ably discussed the theories of rent and profit, as well as some of the most important practical
questions of the day. Cossa, to whom we are indebted for most of these particulars, is himself
author of several works which have established for him a high reputation, as his Scienza delle
Finanze (1875; 4th ed., 1887), and his Primi Elementi di Economia Politica (1875; 8th ed., 1888),
which latter has been translated into several European languages.
Of greater interest than such an imperfect catalogue of writers is the fact of the appearance in Italy
of the economic dualism to which we have referred as characterising our time. There also the two
schoolsthe old or so-called orthodox and the new or historicalwith their respective modified forms,
are found face to face. Cossa tells us that the instructors of the younger economists in northern Italy
were publicly denounced in 1874 as Germanists, socialists, and corrupters of the Italian youth. In
reply to this charge Luzzatti, Lampertico, and Scialoja convoked in Milan the first congress of
economists (1875) with the object of proclaiming their resistance to the idea which was sought to be
imposed on them "that the science was born and died with Adam Smith and his commentators." M.
Émile de Laveleye's interesting Lettres d'Italie (187879) throw light on the state of economic studies
in that country in still more recent years. Minghetti, presiding at the banquet at which M. de Laveleye
was entertained by his Italian brethren, spoke of the" two tendencies "which had manifested
themselves, and implied his own inclination to the new views. Carlo Ferraris, a pupil of Wagner,
follows the same direction. Formal expositions and defences of the historical method have been
produced by R. Schiattarella (Del metodo in Economia Sociale, 1875) and S. Cognetti de Martiis
(Delle attinenze tra l'Economia Sociale e la Storia, 1865). A large measure of acceptance has also
been given to the historical method in learned and judicious monographs by Ricca Salerno (see
especially his essay Del metodo in Econ. Pot., 1878). Luzzatti and Forti for some time edited a
periodical, the Giornale degli Economisti, which was the organ of the new school, but which, when
Cossa wrote, had ceased to appear. Cossa himself, whilst refusing his adhesion to this school on
the ground that it reduces political economy to a mere narrative of facts,an observation which, we
must be permitted to say, betrays an entire misconception of its true principles,admits that it has
been most useful in several ways, and especially as having given the signal for a salutary, though,
as he thinks, an excessive, reaction against the doctrinaire exaggerations of the older theorists.
FRANCE
In France the historical school has not made so strong an impression,partly, no doubt, because the
extreme doctrines of the Ricardian system never obtained much hold there. It was by his recognition
of its freedom from those exaggerations that Jevons was led to declare that" the truth is with the
French school," whilst he pronounced our English economists to have been "living in a fool's
paradise." National prejudice may also have contributed to the result referred to, the ordinary
Frenchman being at present disposed to ask whether any good thing can come out of Germany.
But, as we have shown, the philosophic doctrines on which the whole proceeding of the historical
school is founded were first enunciated by a great French thinker, whose splendid services most of
his fellow-countrymen seem, as yet, very inadequately to appreciate. Perhaps another determining
cause is to be looked for in official influences, which in France, by their action on the higher
education, impede the free movement of independent conviction, as was seen notably in the
temporary éclat they gave on the wider philosophic stage to the shallow eclecticism of Cousin. The
tendency to the historical point of view has appeared in France, as elsewhere; but it has shown itself
not so much in modifying general doctrine as in leading to a more careful study of the economic
opinions and institutions of the past.
Much useful work has been done by Frenchmen (with whom Belgians may here be associated) in
the history of political economy, regarded either as a body of theory or as a systemor series of
systemsof policy. Blanqui's history (183738) is not, indeed, entitled to a very high rank, but it was
serviceable as a first general draft. That of Villeneuve-Bargemont (1839) was also interesting and
useful, as presenting the Catholic view of the development and tendencies of the science. C. Perin's
Les doctrines économiques depuis un siècle (1880) is written from the same point of view. A
number of valuable monographs on particular statesmen or thinkers has also been produced by
Frenchmen,as, for example, that of A. Batbie on Turgot (Turgot Philosophe, Économiste, et
Administrateur, 1861); of A. Neymarck on the same statesman (Turgot et ses doctrines, 1885); of
Pierre Clement on Colbert (Histoire de Colbert et de son Administration, 2d ed., 1875) ; of H.
Baudrillart on Bodin J. Bodin et son Temps; Tableau des Theories politiques et des Idles
économiques au 16 siècle, 1853)', of Léonce de Lavergne on the physiocrats (Les Éconornistes
Français du 18 siècle, 1870). The treatise of M. de Laveleye, De la Proprieté et de ses formes
primitives (1874; Eng. trans. by G. R. Marriott, 1878), is specially worthy of action, not merely for its
array of facts respecting the early forms of property, but because it co-operates strongly with the
tendency of the new school to regard each stage of economic life from the relative point of view, as
resulting from an historic past, harmonising with the entire body of contemporary social conditions,
and bearing in its bosom the germs of a future, predetermined in its essential character, though
modifiable in its secondary dispositions.
M. de Laveleye has done much to call attention to the general principles of the historical school,
acting in this way most usefully as an interpreter between Germany and France. But he appears in
his latest manifesto (Les Lois naturelles et l'objet de l'économie Politique, 1883) to separate himself
from the best members of that school, and to fall into positive error, when he refuses to economics
the character of a true science (or department of a science) as distinguished from an art, and denies
the existence of economic laws or tendencies independent of individual wills. Such a denial seems
to involve that of social laws generally, which is a singularly retrograde attitude for a thinker of our
time to take up, and one which cannot be excused since the appearance of the Philosophic Positive.
The use of the metaphysical phrase "necessary laws " obscures the question; it suffices to speak of
laws which do in fact prevail. M. de Laveleye relies on morals as supplying a parallel case, where
we deal, not with natural laws, but with "imperative prescriptions," as if these prescriptions did not
imply, as their basis, observed coexistences and sequences, and as if there were no such thing as
moral evolution. He seems to be as far from the right point of view in one direction as his opponents
of the old school in another. All that his arguments have really any tendency to prove is the
proposition, undoubtedly a true one, that economic facts cannot be explained by a theory which
leaves out of account the other social aspects, and therefore that our studies and expositions of
economic phenomena must be kept in close relation with the conclusions of the larger science of
society.
We cannot do more than notice in a general way some of the expository treatises of which there has
been an almost continuous series from the time of Say downwards, or indeed from the date of
Germain Gamier's Abégé des Principes de l'économie Politique (1796). That of Destutt de Tracy
forms a portion of his Éléments d'Ideéologie (1823). Droz brought out especially the relations of
economics to morals and of wealth to human happiness (Économie Politique, 1829). Pellegrino
Rossi,an Italian, formed, however, as an economist by studies in Switzerland, professing the
science in Paris, and writing in French (Cours d'économie Politique, 183854),gave in classic form an
exposition of the doctrines of Say, Malthus, and Ricardo. Michel Chevalier (18061879), specially
known in England by his tract, translated by Cobden, on the fall in the value of gold (La Baisse d'Or,
1858), gives in his Cours d'économie Politique (184550) particularly valuable matter on the most
recent industrial phenomena, and on money and the production of the precious metals. Henri
Baudrillart, author of Les Rapports de la Morale et de l'économie Politique (1860; 2d ed., 1883), and
of Histoire du Luxe (1878), published in 1857 a Manuel d'économie Politique (3d ed., 1872), which
Cossa calls an "admirable compendium." Joseph Gamier (Traits de l'économie Politique, 1860; 8th
ed., 1880) in some respects follows Dunoyer. J. G. Courcelle-Senenil, the translator of J. S. Mill,
whom Prof. F. A. Walker regards as "perhaps the ablest economist writing in the French language
since J. B. Say," besides a Traité théorique et pratique des opérations de Banque and Théorie des
Enterprises Industrielles (1856), wrote a Traité d'économic Politique (185859; 2d ed., 1867), which
is held in much esteem. Finally, the Genevese, Antoine Élise Cherbuliez (d. 1869), was author of
what Cossa pronounces to be the best treatise on the science in the French language (Précis de la
Science économique, 1862). L. Walras, in Éléments d'économie Politique pure (187477), and
Théorie Mathematique de la Richesse Sociale (1883), has followed the example of Cournot in
attempting a mathematical treatment of the subject.
ENGLAND
Sacrificing the strict chronological order of the history of economics to deeper considerations, we
have already spoken of Cairnes, describing him as the last original English writer who was an
adherent of the old school pure and simple. Both in method and doctrine he was essentially
Ricardian; though professing and really feeling profound respect for Mill, he was disposed to go
behind him and attach himself rather to their common master. Mr. Sidgwick is doubtless right in
believing that his Leading Principles did much to shake "the unique prestige which Mill's exposition
had enjoyed for nearly half a generation," and in this, as in some other ways, Cairnes may have
been a dissolving force, and tended towards radical change; but, if he exercised this influence, he
did so unconsciously and involuntarily. Many influences had, however, for some time been silently
sapping the foundations of the old system. The students of Comte had seen that its method was an
erroneous one. The elevated moral teaching of Carlyle had disgusted the best minds with the low
maxims of the Manchester school. Ruskin had not merely protested against the egoistic spirit of the
prevalent doctrine, but had pointed to some of its real weaknesses as a scientific theory.(10) It
began to be felt, and even its warmest partisans sometimes admitted, that it had done all the work,
mainly a destructive one, of which it was capable. Cairnes himself declared that, whilst most
educated people believed it doomed to sterility for the future, some energetic minds thought it likely
to be a positive obstruction in the way of useful reform. Miss Martineau, who had in earlier life been
a thorough Ricardian, came to think that political economy, as it had been elaborated by her
contemporaries, was, strictly speaking, no science at all, and must undergo such essential change
that future generations would owe little to it beyond the establishment of the existence of general
laws in one department of human affairs.(11) The instinctive repugnance of the working classes had
continued, in spite of the efforts of their superiors to recommend its lessons to themefforts which
were perhaps not unfrequently dictated rather by class interest than by public spirit. All the
symptoms boded impending change, but they were visible rather in general literature and in the
atmosphere of social opinion than within the economic circle.(12) But when it became known that a
great movement had taken place, especially in Germany, on new and more hopeful lines, the
English economists themselves began to recognize the necessity of a reform and even to further its
advent. The principal agencies of this kind, in marshalling the way to a renovation of the science,
have been those of Bagehot, Leslie, and Jevons,the first limiting the sphere of the dominant system,
while seeking to conserve it within narrower bounds; the second directly assailing it and setting up
the new method as the rival and destined successor of the old; and the third acknowledging the col.
lapse of the hitherto reigning dynasty, proclaiming the necessity of an altered regime, and admitting
the younger claimant as joint possessor in the future. Thus, in England too, the dualism which exists
on the Continent has been established; and there is reason to expect that here more speedily and
decisively than in France or Italy the historical school will displace its antagonist. It is certainly in
England next after Germany that the preaching of the new views has been most vigorously and
effectively begun.
Walter Bagehot (18261877) was author of an excellent work on the English money market and the
circumstances which have determined its peculiar character (Lombard Street, 1873; 8th ed., 1882),
and of several monographs on particular monetary questions, which his practical experience,
combined with his scientific habits of thought, eminently fitted him to handle. On the general
principles of economics he wrote some highly important essays collected in Economic Studies
(edited by R. H. Hutton, 1880), the object of which was to show that the traditional system of political
economythe system of Ricardo and J. S. Mill rested on certain fundamental assumptions, which,
instead of being universally true in fact, were only realised within very narrow limits of time and
space. Instead of being applicable to all states of society, it holds only in relation to those "in which
commerce has largely developed, and where it has taken the form of development, or something
like the form, which it has taken in England." It is "the science of business such as business is in
large and trading communitiesan analysis of the great commerce by which England has become
rich." But more than this it is not; it will not explain the economic life of earlier times, nor even of
other communities in our own time; and for the latter reason it has remained insular; it has never
been fully accepted in other countries as it has been at home. It is, in fact, a sort of ready reckoner,
enabling us to calculate roughly what will happen under given conditions in Lombard Street, on the
Stock Exchange, and in the great markets of the world. It is a " convenient series of deductions from
assumed axioms which are never quite true, which in many times and countries would be utterly
untrue, but which are sufficiently near to the principal conditions of the modern " English" world to
make it useful to consider them by themselves."
Mill and Cairnes had already shown that the science they taught was a hypothetic one, in the sense
that it dealt not with real but with imaginary men"economic men" who were conceived as simply
"money-making animals." But Bagehot went further: he showed what those writers may have
indicated, but had not clearly brought out,(13) that the world in which these men were supposed to
act is also "a very limited and peculiar world." What marks off this special world, he tells us, is the
promptness of transfer of capital and labour from one employment to another, as determined by
differences in the remuneration of those several employments-a promptness about the actual
existence of which in the contemporary English world he fluctuates a good deal, but which on the
whole he recognizes as substantially realised.
Bagehot described himself as "the last man of the ante-Mill period," having learned his economics
from Ricardo; and the latter writer he appears to have to the end greatly over-estimated. But he lived
long enough to gain some knowledge of the historical method, and with it he had "no quarrel but
rather much sympathy." "Rightly conceived," he said, "it is no rival to the abstract method rightly
conceived." We will not stop to criticise a second time the term "abstract method" here applied to
that of the old school, or to insist on the truth that all science is necessarily abstract, the only
question that can arise being as to the just degree of abstraction, or, in general, as to the right
constitution of the relation between the abstract and the concrete. It is more apposite to remark that
Bagehot's view of the reconciliation of the two methods is quite different from that of most "orthodox"
economists. They commonly treat the historical method with a sort of patronising toleration as
affording useful exemplifications or illustrations of their theorems. But, according to him, the two
methods are applicable in quite different fields. For what he calls the " abstract " method he reserves
the narrow, but most immediately interesting, province of modern advanced industrial life, and
hands over to the historical the economic phenomena of all the human past and all the rest of the
human present. He himself exhibits much capacity for such historical research, and in particular has
thrown real light on the less-noticed economic and social effects of the institution of money, and on
the creation of capital in the earlier stages of society. But his principal efficacy has been in reducing,
by the considerations we have mentioned, still further than his predecessors had done, our
conceptions of the work which the a priori method can do. He in fact dispelled the idea that it can
ever supply the branch of general Sociology which deals with wealth. As to the relations of
economics to the other sides of Sociology, he holds that the "abstract" science rightly ignores them.
It does not consider the differences of human wants, or the social results of their several
gratifications, except so far as these affect the production of wealth. In its view "a pot of beer and a
picturea book of religion and a pack of cardsare equally worthy of regard." It therefore leaves the
ground open for a science which will, on the one hand, study wealth as a social fact in all its
successive forms and phases, and, on the other, will regard it in its true light as an instrument for the
conservation and evolutionmoral as well as materialof human societies.
Though it will involve a slight digression, it is desirable here to notice a further attenuation of the
functions of the deductive method, which is well pointed out in Mr. Sidgwick's remarkable work on
political economy. He observes that, whilst J. S. Mill declares that the method a priori is the true
method of the science, and that "it has been so understood and taught by all its most distinguished
teachers," he yet himself in the treatment of production followed an inductive method (or at least one
essentially different from the deductive), obtaining his results by "merely analysing and
systematising our common empirical knowledge of the facts of industry." To explain this
characteristic inconsistency, Mr. Sidgwick suggests that Mill, in making his general statement as to
method, had in contemplation only the statics of distribution and exchange. And in this latter field
Mr. Sidgwick holds that the a priori method, if it be pursued with caution, if the simplified premises
be well devised and the conclusions "modified by a rough conjectural allowance" for the elements
omitted in the premises, is not, for the case of a developed industrial society, "essentially false or
misleading." Its conclusions are hypothetically valid, though "its utility as a means of interpreting and
explaining concrete facts depends on its being used with as full a knowledge as possible of the
results of observation and induction." We do not think this statement need be objected to, though we
should prefer to regard deduction from hypothesis as a useful occasional logical artifice, and, as
such, perfectly legitimate in this as in other fields of inquiry, rather than as the main form of method
in any department of economics. Mr. Sidgwick, by his limitation of deduction in distributional
questions to "a state of things taken as the type to which civilized society generally approximates,"
seems to agree with Bagehot that for times and places which do not correspond to this type the
historical method must be used a method which, be it observed, does not exclude, but positively
implies, " reflective analysis " of the facts, and their interpretation from "the motives of human
agents" as well as from other determining conditions. In the dynamical study of wealthof the
changes in its distribution no less than its productionMr. Sidgwick admits that the method a priori
"can occupy but a very subordinate place." We should say that here also, though to a less extent, as
a logical artifice it may sometimes be useful, though the hypotheses assumed ought not to be the
same that are adapted to a mature industrial stage. But the essential organ must be the historical
method, studying comparatively the different phases of social evolution.
Connected with the theory of modern industry is one subject which Bagehot treated, though only in
an incidental way, much more satisfactorily than his predecessors, namely, the function of the
entrepreneur, who in Mill and Cairnes is scarcely recognized except as the owner of capital. It is
quite singular how little, in the Leading Principles of the latter, his active co-operation is taken into
account. Bagehot objects to the phrase "wages of superintendence," commonly used to express his
"reward," as suggesting altogether erroneous ideas of the nature of his work, and well describes the
large and varied range of his activity and usefulness, and the rare combination of gifts and
acquirements which go to make up the perfection of his equipment. It can scarcely be doubted that
a foregone conclusion in favour of the system of (so-called) co-operation has sometimes led
economists to keep these important considerations in the background. They have been brought into
due prominence of late in the treatises of Profs. Marshall and F. A. Walker, who, however, have
scarcely made clear, and certainly have not justified, the principle on which the amount of the
remuneration of the entrepreneur is determined.
We have seen that Jones had in his dogmatic teaching anticipated in some degree the attitude of
the new school; important works had also been produced, notably by Thomas Tooke and William
Newmarch (History of Prices, 18381857), and by James E. Thorold Rogers (History of Agriculture
and Prices in England, 186682),(14) on the course of English economic history. But the first
systematic statement by an English writer of the philosophic foundation of the historical method, as
the appropriate organ of economic research, is to be found in an essay by T. E. Cliffe Leslie (printed
in the Dublin University periodical, Hermathena, 1876; since included in his Essays Moral and
Political, 1879). This essay was the most important publication on the logical aspect of economic
science which had appeared since Mill's essay in his Unsettled Questions; though Cairnes had
expanded and illustrated the views of Mill, he had really added little to their substance. Leslie takes
up a position directly opposed to theirs. He criticises with much force and verve the principles and
practice of the "orthodox" school. Those who are acquainted with what has been written on this
subject by Knies and other Germans will appreciate the freshness and originality of Leslie's
treatment. He points out the loose and vague character of the principle to which the classical
economists profess to trace back all the phenomena with which they dealnamely, the "desire of
wealth." This phrase really stands for a variety of wants, desires, and sentiments, widely different in
their nature and economic effects, and undergoing important changes (as, indeed, the component
elements of wealth itself also do) in the several successive stages of the social movement. The truth
is that there are many "different economic motors, altruistic as well as egoistic; and they cannot all
be lumped together by such a coarse generalisation. The a priori and purely deductive method
cannot yield an explanation of the causes which regulate either the nature or the amount of wealth,
nor of the varieties of distribution in different social systems, as, for example, in those of France and
England. "The whole economy of every nation is the result of a long evolution in which there has
been both continuity and change, and of which the economical side is only a particular aspect. And
the laws of which it is the result must be sought in history and the general laws of society and social
evolution." The intellectual, moral, legal, political, and economic sides of social progress are
indissolubly connected. Thus, juridical facts relating to property, occupation, and trade, thrown up by
the social movement, are also economic facts. And, more generally, "the economic condition of
English" or any other "society at this day is the outcome of the entire movement which has evolved
the political constitution, the structure of the family, the forms of religion, the learned professions,
the arts and sciences, the state of agriculture, manufactures, and commerce." To understand
existing economic relations we must trace their historical evolution; and "the philosophical method of
political economy must be one which expounds that evolution." This essay was a distinct challenge
addressed to the ideas of the old school on method, and, though its conclusions have been
protested against, the arguments on which they are founded have never been answered.
With respect to the dogmatic generalisations of the "orthodox" economists, Leslie thought some of
them were false, and all of them required careful limitation. Early in his career he had shown the
hollowness of the wage-fund theory, though he was not the first to repudiate it.(15) The doctrine of
an average rate of wages and an average rate of profits he rejected except under the restrictions
stated by Adam Smith, which imply a "simple and almost stationary condition" of the industrial world.
He thought the glib assumption of an average rate of wages, as well as of a wage-fund, had done
much harm "by hiding the real rates of wages, the real causes which govern them, and the real
sources from which wages proceed." The facts, which he laboriously collected, he found to be
everywhere against the theory. In every country there is really "a great number of rates; and the real
problem is, What are the causes which produce these different rates?" As to profits, he denies that
there are any means of knowing the gain; and prospects of all the investments of capital, and
declares it to be a mere fiction that any capitalist surveys the whole field. Bagehot, as we saw, gave
up the doctrine of a national level of wages and profits except in the peculiar case of an industrial
society of the contemporary English type; Leslie denies it even for such a society. With this doctrine,
that of cost of production as determining price collapses, and the principle emerges that it is not cost
of production, but demand and supply, on which domestic, no less than international, values
depend,though this formula will require much interpretation before it can be used safely and with
advantage. Thus Leslie extends to the whole of the national industry the partial negation of the older
dogma introduced by Cairnes through the idea of non-competing groups. He does not, of course,
dispute the real operation of cost of production on price in the limited area within which rates of
profit and wages are determinate and known; but he maintains that its action on the large scale is
too remote and uncertain to justify our treating it as regulator of price. Now, if this be so, the entire
edifice which Ricardo reared on the basis of the identity of cost of production and price, with its
apparent but unreal simplicity, symmetry, and completeness, disappears; and the ground is cleared
for the new structure which must take its place. Leslie predicts that, if political economy, under that
name, does not bend itself to the task of rearing such a structure, the office will speedily be taken
out of its hands by Sociology.
Leslie was a successful student of several special economic subjectsof agricultural economy, of
taxation, of the distribution of the precious metals and the history of prices, and, as has been
indicated, of the movements of wages. But it is in relation to the method and fundamental doctrines
of the science that he did the most important, because the most opportune and needful work. And,
though his course was closed too early for the interests of knowledge, and much of what he
produced was merely occasional and fragmentary, his services will be found to have been greater
than those of many who have left behind them more systematic, elaborate, and pretentious writings.
One of the most original of recent English writers on Political Economy was W. Stanley Jevons
(18351882). The combination which he presented of a predilection and aptitude for exact statistical
inquiry with sagacity and ingenuity in the interpretation of the results was such as might remind us of
Petty. He tended strongly to bring economics into close relation with physical science. He made a
marked impression on the public mind by his attempt to take stock of our resources in the article of
coal. His idea of a relation between the recurrences of commercial crises and the period of the sun-
spots gave evidence of a fertile and bold scientific imagination, though he cannot be said to have
succeeded in establishing such a relation. He was author of an excellent treatise on Money and the
Mechanism of Exchange (1875), and of various essays on currency and finance, which have been
collected since his death, and contain vigorous discussions on subjects of this nature, as on
bimetallism (with a decided tendency in favour of the single gold standard), and several valuable
suggestions, as with respect to the most perfect system of currency, domestic and international, and
in particular the extension of the paper currency in England to smaller denominations. He proposed
in other writings (collected in Methods of Social Reform, 1883) a variety of measures, only partly
economic in their character, directed especially to the elevation of the working classes, one of the
most important being in relation to the conditions of the labour of married women in factories. This
was one of several instances in which he repudiated the laisser faire principle, which, indeed, in his
book on The State in Relation to Labour (1882), he refuted in the clearest and most convincing way,
without changing the position he had always maintained as an advocate of free trade. Towards the
end of his career, which was prematurely terminated, he was more and more throwing off "the
incubus of metaphysical ideas and expressions "which still impeded the recognition or confused the
appreciation of social facts. He was, in his own words, ever more distinctly coming to the conclusion
" that the only hope of attaining a true system of economics is to fling aside, once and for ever, the
mazy and preposterous assumptions of the Ricardian school." With respect to method, though he
declares it to be his aim to "investigate inductively the intricate phenomena of trade and industry,"
his views had not perhaps assumed a definitive shape. The editor of some of his remains declines
to undertake the determination of his exact position with respect to the historical school. The fullest
indications we possess on that subject are to be found in a lecture of 1876, On the Future of
Political Economy. He saw the importance and necessity in economics of historical investigation, a
line of study which he himself was led by native bent to prosecute in some directions. But he
scarcely apprehended the full meaning of the historical method, which he erroneously contrasted
with the "theoretical," and apparently supposed to be concerned only with verifying and illustrating
certain abstract doctrines resting on independent bases. Hence, whilst he declared himself in favour
of "thorough reform and reconstruction," he sought to preserve the a priori mode of proceeding
alongside of, and concurrently with, the historical. Political economy, in fact, he thought was
breaking up and falling into several, probably into many, different branches of inquiry, prominent
amongst which would be the "theory" as it had descended from his best predecessors, especially
those of the French school, whilst another would be the "historical study," as it was followed in
England by Jones, Rogers, and others, and as it had been proclaimed in general principle by his
contemporary Cliffe Leslie. This was one of those eclectic views which have no permanent validity,
but are useful in facilitating a transition. The two methods will doubtless for a time coexist, but the
historical will inevitably supplant its rival. What Jevons meant as the "theory" he wished to treat by
mathematical methods (see his Theory of Political Economy, 1871; 2d ed., 1879). This project had,
as we have seen, been entertained and partially carried into effect by others before him, though he
unduly multiplies the number of such earlier essays when, for example, he mentions Ricardo and J.
S. Mill as writing mathematically because they sometimes illustrated the meaning of their
propositions by dealing with definite arithmetical quantities. Such illustrations, of which a specimen
is supplied by Mill's treatment of the subject of international trade, have really nothing to do with the
use of mathematics as an instrument for economic research, or even for the co-ordination of
economic truths. We have already, in speaking of Cournot, explained why, as it seems to us, the
application of mathematics in the higher sense to economics must necessarily fail, and we do not
think that it succeeded in Jevons's hands. His conception of "final utility" is ingenious. But it is no
more than a mode of presenting the notion of price in the case of commodities homogeneous in
quality and admitting of increase by infinitestimal additions; and the expectation of being able by
means of it to subject economic doctrine to a mathematical method will be found illusory. He offers
(16) as the result of a hundred pages of mathematical reasoning what he calls a "curious
conclusion,"(17) in which "the keystone of the whole theory of exchange and of the principal
problems of economics lies." This is the proposition that "the ratio of exchange of any two
commodities will be the reciprocal of the ratio of the final degrees of utility of the quantities of
commodity available for consumption after the exchange is completed." Now as long as we remain
in the region of the metaphysical entities termed utilities, this theorem is unverifiable and indeed
unintelligible, because we have no means of estimating quantitatively the mental impression of final,
or any other, utility. But when we translate it into the language of real life, measuring the "utility" of
anything to a man by what he will give for it, the proposition is at once seen to be a truism. What
Jevons calls "final utility" being simply the price per unit of quantity, the theorem states that, in an
act of exchange, the product of the quantity of the commodity given by its price per unit of quantity
(estimated in a third article) is the same as the corresponding product for the commodity receiveda
truth so obvious as to require no application of the higher mathematics to discover it. If we cannot
look for results more substantial than this, there is not much encouragement to pursue such
researches, which will in fact never be anything more than academic playthings, and which involve
the very real evil of restoring the "metaphysical ideas and expressions previously discarded. The
reputation of Jevons as an acute and vigorous thinker, inspired with noble popular sympathies, is
sufficiently established. But the attempt to represent him, in spite of himself, as a follower and
continuator of Ricardo, and as one of the principal authors of the development of economic theory
(meaning by "theory" the old a priori doctrine) can only lower him in estimation by placing his
services on grounds which will not bear criticism. His name will survive m connection, not with new
theoretical constructions, but with his treatment of practical problems, his fresh and lively
expositions, and, as we have shown, his energetic tendency to a renovation of economic method.
Arnold Toynbee (18521883), who left behind him a beautiful memory, filled as he was with the love
of truth and an ardent and active zeal for the public good, was author of some fragmentary or
unfinished pieces, which yet well deserve attention both for their intrinsic merit and as indicating the
present drift of all the highest natures, especially amongst our younger men, in the treatment of
economic questions.(18) He had a belief in the organizing power of democracy which it is not easy
to share, and some strange ideas due to youthful enthusiasm, such as, for example, that Mazzini is
"the true teacher of our age;" and he fluctuates considerably in his opinion of the Ricardian political
economy, in one place declaring it to be a detected "intellectual imposture," whilst elsewhere,
apparently under the influence of Bagehot, he speaks of it as having been in recent times "only
corrected, re-stated, and put into the proper relation to the science of life," meaning apparently, by
this last, general sociology. He saw, however, that our great help in the future must come, as much
had already come, from the historical method, to which in his own researches he gave preponderant
weight. Its true character, too, he understood better than many even of those who have commended
it; for he perceived that it not merely explains the action of special local or temporary conditions or
economic phenomena, but seeks, by comparing the stages of social development in different
countries and times, to "discover laws of universal application." If, as we are told, there exists at
Oxford a rising group of men who occupy a position in regard to economic thought substantially
identical with that of Toynbee, the fact is one of good omen for the future of the science.
AMERICA
For a long time, as we have already observed, little was done by America in the field of Economics.
The most obvious explanation of this fact, which holds with respect to philosophical studies
generally, is the absorption of the energies of the nation in practical pursuits. Further reasons are
suggested in two instructive Essaysone by Professor Charles F. Dunbar in the North American
Review, 1876, the other by Cliffe Leslie in the Fortnightly Review for October 1880.
We have already referred to the Report on Manufactures by Alexander Hamilton; and the memorial
drawn up by Albert Gallatin (1832), and presented to Congress from the Philadelphia Convention in
favour of Tariff reform, deserves to be mentioned as an able statement of the arguments against
protection. Three editions of the Wealth of Nations appeared in America, in 1789, 1811, and 1818,
and Ricardo's principal work was reprinted there in 1819. The treatises of Daniel Raymond (1820),
Thomas Cooper (1826), Willard Phillips (1828), Francis Wayland (1837), and Henry Vethake (1838)
made known the principles arrived at by Adam Smith and some of his successors. Rae, a
Scotchman settled in Canada, published (1834) a book entitled New Principles of Political
Economy, which has been highly praised by J. S. Mill (bk. i. chap. ii), especially for its treatment of
the causes which determine the accumulation of capital. The principal works which afterwards
appeared down to the time of the Civil War were Francis Bowen's Principles of Political Economy,
1856, afterwards entitled American Political Economy, 1870; John Bascom's Political Economy,
1859; and Stephen Colwell's Ways and Means of Payment, 1859. In the period including and
following the war appeared Amasa Walker's Science of Wealth, 1866; i8th ed., 1883, and A. L.
Perry's Elements of Political Economy, 1866. A. Walker and Perry are free-traders; Perry is a
disciple of Bastiat. Of Carey we have already spoken at some length ; his American followers are E.
Peshine Smith (A Manual of Political Economy, 1853), William Elder (Questions of the Day, 1871),
and Robert E. Thompson (Social Science, 1875). The name of no American economist stands
higher than that of General Francis A Walker (son of Amasa Walker), author of special works on the
Wages Question (1876) and on Money (1878), as well as of an excellent general treatise on Political
Economy (1883; 2d ed. 1887). Early works on American economic history are those of A. S. Bolles,
entitled Industrial History of the United States (1878), and Financial History of the United States,
17741885, published in 1879 and later years.
The deeper and more comprehensive study of the subject which has of late years prevailed in
America, added to influences from abroad, has given rise, there also, to a division of economists
into two schoolsan old and a new similar to those which we have found confronting each other
elsewhere. A meeting was held at Saratoga in September 1885, at which a society was founded,
called the American Economic Association. The object of this movement was to oppose the idea
that the field of economic research was closed, and to promote a larger and more fruitful study of
economic questions. The same spirit led to the establishment of the Quarterly Journal of
Economics, published at Boston for Harvard University. The first article in this Journal was by C. F.
Dunbar, whose review of a Century of American Political Economy we have already noticed; and in
this article he set out, in the interest of conciliation, the tendencies of the two schools.
This division of opinion was manifested in a striking way by a discussion on the method and
fundamental principles of Economics, which was conducted in the pages of the periodical entitled
Science, and has since been reproduced in a separate form (Science Economic Discussion, New
York, 1886). In this controversy the views of the new school were expounded and advocated with
great ability. The true nature of economic method, the relativity both of economic institutions and of
economic thought, arising from their dependence on varying social conditions, the close connection
of economic doctrine with contemporary jurisprudence, the necessity of keeping economics in
harmony with social ethics, and the importance of a study of consumption (denied by J. S. Mill and
others) were all exhibited with remarkable clearness and force.(19) There is every reason to believe
with Leslie that America will take an active part both in bringing to light the economic problems of
the future and in working out their solution.
Notes:
1. It would be a grave error to suppose that the subjection of social phenomena to natural laws
affords any encouragement to a spirit of fatalistic quietism. On the contrary, it is the existence of
such laws that is the necessary basis of all systematic action for the improvement either of our
condition or of our nature, as may be seen by considering the parallel case of hygienic and
thereapeutic agencies. And, since the different orders of phenomena are more modifiable in
proportion to their greater complexity, the social field admits of more extensive and efficacious
human intervention than the inorganic or vital domain. In relation to the dynamical side of Sociology,
whilst the direction and essential character of the evolution are predetermined, its rate and
secondary features are capable of modification.
2. He had already in 1822 stated his fundamental principles in an epuscule which is reproduced in
the Appendix to his Politique Positive.
3. Under the influence of these views of Comte, J. S. Mill attempted in Book IV. of his Political
Economy a treatment of Economic Dynamics; but that appears to us one of the least satisfactory
portions of his work.
4. This phraseology was probably borrowed from the controversy on the method of jurisprudence
between Thibaut on the one hand and Savigny and the school of Hugo on the other.
5. It will in each case be necessary to examine whether the action can best be taken by the central,
or by the local, government.
6. This should be remembered by readers of M. Leroy-Beaulieu's work on Collectivism (1884), in
which be treats Schäffle as the principal theoretic representative of that form of socialism.
7. By the present writer; being an Address to the Section of Economic Science and Statistics of the
British Association at its meeting in Dublin in 1878.
8. Guide to the Study of Political Economy, 1880. See also the Bibliographical matter in his Primi
Elementi di E. P., vol. i, 8th ed., 1888.
9. See his Saggi di Economia Politica. 1881
10. The remarkable book Money and Morals, by John Lalor, 1852. was written partly under the
influence of Carlyle. There is a good monograph entitled John Ruskin's, Economist, by P. Geddes,
1884.
11. See her Autobiogaphy. 2d ed., vol. ii, p. 244.
12. A vigorous attack on the received system was made by David Syme in his Outlines of an
Industrial Science, 1876.
13. Jones, whose writings were apparently unknown to Bagehot, had. as we have seen, in some
degree anticipated him in his exposition.
14. Mr Rogers has since continued this work, and has also published The First Nine Years of the
Bank of England, 1887.
15. That service was due to F. D. Lange (Refutation of the Wage-Fund Theory of Modern Political
Economy, 1866). Leslie's treatment of the subject was contained in an article of Fraser's Magazine
for July 1868. reprinted as an appendix to his Land-Systems and Industrial Economy of Ireland.
England, and Continental Countries, 1870.
16. Theory of Political Economy. 2d ed., p. 103.
17. Fortnightly Review for November 1876, p. 617.
18. See his Lectures on The Industrial Revolution in England, with Memoir by the Master of Balliol,
1884; 2d ed., 1887.
19. The contributors on the side of the new school were Dr. Edwin R. A. Seligman, Professor E. J.
James, Professor Richard T. Ely, Henry C. Adams, Richmond Mayo Smith, and Simon N. Patten.
The representatives of the old school were Professor Simon Newcomb, F. W. Taussig, and Arthur
T. Hadley.
CHAPTER VII
CONCLUSION
Let us briefly consider in conclusion, by the light of the preceding historical survey, what appear to
be the steps in the direction of a renovation of economic science which are now at once practicable
and urgent.
I. Economic investigation has hitherto fallen for the most part into the hands of lawyers and men of
letters, not into those of a genuinely scientific class. Nor have its cultivators in general had that
sound preparation in the sciences of inorganic and vital nature which is necessary whether as
supplying bases of doctrine or as furnishing lessons of method. Their education has usually been of
a metaphysical kind Hence political economy has retained much of the form and spirit which
belonged to it in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, instead of advancing with the times, and
assuming a truly positive character. It is homogeneous with the school logic, with the abstract
unhistorical jurisprudence, with the a priori ethics and politics, and other similar antiquated systems
of thought; and it will be found that those who insist most strongly on the maintenance of its
traditional character have derived their habitual mental pabulum from those regions of obsolete
speculation. We can thus understand the attitude of true men of science towards this branch of
study, which they regard with ill-disguised contempt, and to whose professors they either refuse or
very reluctantly concede a place in their brotherhood.
The radical vice of this unscientific character of political economy seems to lie in the too individual
and subjective aspect under which it has been treated. Wealth having been conceived as what
satisfies desires, the definitely determinable qualities possessed by some objects of supplying
physical energy, and improving the physiological constitution, are left out of account. Everything is
gauged by the standard of subjective notions and desires. All desires are viewed as equally
legitimate, and all that satisfies our desires as equally wealth. Value being regarded as the result of
a purely mental appreciation, the social value of things in the sense of their objective utility, which is
often scientifically measurable, is passed over, and ratio of exchange is exclusively considered. The
truth is, that at the bottom of all economic investigation must lie the idea of the destination of wealth
for the maintenance and evolution of a society. And, if we overlook this, our economics will become
a play of logic or a manual for the market, rather than a contribution to social science; whilst wearing
an air of completeness, they will be in truth one-sided and superficial. Economic science is
something far larger than the Catallactics to which some have wished to reduce it A special merit of
the physiocrats seems to have lain in their vague perception of the close relation of their study to
that of external nature; and, so far, we must recur to their point of view, basing our economics on
physics and biology as developed in our own time.(1) Further, the science must be cleared of all the
theologico-metaphysical elements or tendencies which still encumber and deform it. Teleology and
optimism on the one hand, and the jargon of "natural liberty" and "indefeasible rights" on the other,
must be finally abandoned.
Nor can we assume as universal premises, from which economic truths can be deductively derived,
the convenient formulas which have been habitually employed, such as hat all men desire wealth
and dislike exertion. These vague propositions, which profess to anticipate and supersede social
experience, and which necessarily introduce the absolute where relativity should reign, must be laid
aside. The laws of wealth (to reverse a phrase of Buckle's) must be inferred from the facts of wealth,
not from the postulate of human selfishness. We must bend ourselves to a serious lirect study of the
way in which society has actually addressed itself and now addresses itself to its own conservation
and evolution through the supply of its material wants. What organs it has developed for this
purpose, how they operate, how they are affected by the medium in which they act and by the
coexistent organs directed to other ends how in their turn they react on those latter, how they and
their functions are progressively modified in process of tine these problems, whether sta tical or
dynamical, are all questions of fact, as capable of being studied through observation and history as
the nature and progress of human language or religion, or any other group of social phenomena.
Such study will of course require a continued "reflective analysis "of the results of observation; and,
whilst eliminating all premature assumptions, we shall use ascertainec truths respecting human
nature as guides in the inquiry and aids towards the interpretation of facts. And the employment of
deliberately instituted hypotheses will be legitimate, but only as an occasional logical artifice.
II. Economics must be constantly regarded as forming only one department of the larger science of
Sociology, in vital connection with its other departments, and with the moral synthesis which is the
crown of the whole intellectual system. We have already sufficiently explained the philosophical
grounds for the conclusion that the economic phenomena of society cannot be isolated, except
provision ally, from the rest,that, in fact, all the primary social elements should be habitually
regarded with respect to their mutual dependence and reciprocal actions. Especially must we keep
in view the high moral issues to which the economic movement is subservient, and in the absence
of which it could never in any great degree attract the interest or fix the attention either of eminent
thinkers or of right-minded men. The individual point of view will have to be subordinated to the
social; each agent will have to be regarded as an organ of the society to which he belongs and of
the larger society of the race. The consideration of interests, as George Eliot has well said, must
give place to that of functions. The old doctrine of right, which lay at the basis of the system of "
natural liberty," has done its temporary work; a doctrine of duty will have to be substituted, fixing on
positive grounds the nature of the social co-operation of each class and each member of the
community, and the rules which must regulate its just and beneficial exercise.
Turning now from the question of the theoretic constitution of economics, and viewing the science
with respect to its influence on public policy, we need not at the present day waste words in
repudiating the idea that "non-government "in the economic sphere is the normal order of things.
The laisser-faire doctrine, coming down to us from the system of natural liberty, was long the great
watchword of economic orthodoxy. It had a special acceptance and persistence in England in
consequence of the political struggle for the repeal of the corn laws, which made economic
discussion in this country turn almost altogether on free tradea state of things which was continued
by the effort to procure a modification of the protective policy of foreign nations. But it has now for
some time lost the sacrosanct character with which it was formerly invested. This is a result not so
much of scientific thought as of the pressure of practical needsa cause which has modified the
successive forms of economic opinion more than theorists are willing to acknowledge. Social
exigencies will force the hands of statesmen, whatever their attachment to abstract formulas; and
politicians have practically turned their backs on laisser faire. The State has with excellent effect
proceeded a considerable way in the direction of controlling, for ends of social equity or public utility,
the operations of individual interest. The economists themselves have for the most part been
converted on the question; amongst theorists Herbert Spencer found himself almost a vox clamantis
in deserto in protesting against what he called the new slavery" of Governmental interference. He
will protest in vain, so far as he seeks to rehabilitate the old absolute doctrine of the economic
passivity of the State. But it is certainly possible that even by virtue of the force of the reaction
against that doctrine there may be an excessive or precipitate tendency in the opposite direction.
With the course of production or exchange considered in itself there will probably be in England little
disposition to meddle. But the dangers and inconveniences which arise from the unsettled condition
of the world of labour will doubtless from time to time here, as elsewhere, prompt to premature
attempts at regulation. Apart, however, from the removal of evils which threaten the health of the
workers or the public peace, and from temporary palliatives to ease off social pressure, the right
policy of the State in this sphere will for the present be one of abstention. It is indeed certain that
industrial society will not permanently remain without a systematic organization. The mere conflict of
private interests will never produce a well-ordered commonwealth of labour. Freiheit ist keine
Lessung. Freedom is for society, as for the individual, the necessary condition precedent of the
solution of practical problems, both as allowing natural forces to develop themselves and as
exhibiting their spontaneous tendencies; but it is not in itself the solution. Whilst, however, an
organization of the industrial world may with certainty be expected to arise in process of time, it
would be a great error to attempt to improvise one. We are now in a period of transition. Our ruling
powers have still an equivocal character; they are not in real harmony with industrial life, and are in
all respects imperfectly imbued with the modern spirit. Besides the conditions of the new order are
not yet sufficiently understood. The institutions of the future must be founded on sentiments and
habits, and these must be the slow growth of thought and experience. The solution, indeed, must be
at all times largely a moral one; it is the spiritual rather than the temporal power that is the natural
agency for redressing or mitigating most of the evils associated with industrial life.(2) In fact, if there
is a tendencyand we may admit that such a tendency is real or imminentto push the State towards
an extension of the normal limits of its action for the maintenance of social equity, this is doubtless
in some measure due to the fact that the growing dissidence on religious questions in the most
advanced communities has weakened the authority of the Churches, and deprived their influence of
social universality. What is now most urgent is not legislative interference on any large scale with
the industrial relations, but the formation, in both the higher and lower regions of the industrial world,
of profound convictions as to social duties, and some more effective mode than at present exists of
diffusing, maintaining, and applying those convictions. This is a subject into which we cannot enter
here. But it may at least be said that the only parties in contemporary public life which seem rightly
to conceive or adequately to appreciate the necessities of the situation are those that aim, on the
one hand, at the restoration of the old spiritual power, or, on the other, at the formation of a new
one. And this leads to the conclusion that there is one sort of Governmental interference which the
advocates of laisser faire have not always discountenanced, and which yet, more than any other,
tends to prevent the gradual and peaceful rise of a new industrial and social system,namely, the
interference with spiritual liberty by setting up official types of philosophical doctrine, and imposing
restrictions on the expression and discussion of opinions.
It will be seen that our principal conclusion respecting economic action harmonises with that relating
to the theoretic study of economic phenomena. For, as we held that the latter could not be
successfully pursued except as a duly subordinated branch of the wider science of Sociology, so in
practical human affairs we believe that no partial synthesis is possible, but that an economic
reorganization of society implies a universal renovation, intellectual and moral no less than material.
The industrial reformation for which western Europe groans and travails, and the advent of which is
indicated by so many symptoms (though it will come only as the fruit of faithful and sustained effort),
will be no isolated fact, but will form part of an applied art of life, modifying our whole environment,
affecting our whole culture, and regulating our whole conductin a word, directing all our resources to
the one great end of the conservation and development of Humanity.
Notes:
1. This aspect of the subject has been ably treated in papers contributed to the Proceedings of the
Royal Society of Edinburgh on several occasion, during and since 1881 by Mr. P. Geddes, well
known as a biologist.
2. The neglect of this consideration, and the consequent undue exaltation of State action, which,
though quite legitimate, is altogether insufficient, appears to be the principal danger to which the
contemporary German school of economists is exposed. When Schmoller says, "The State is the
grandest existing ethical institution for the education of the human race," he transfers to it the
functions of the Church. The educational action of the State must be, in the main, only indirect.
Livros Grátis
( http://www.livrosgratis.com.br )
Milhares de Livros para Download:
Baixar livros de Administração
Baixar livros de Agronomia
Baixar livros de Arquitetura
Baixar livros de Artes
Baixar livros de Astronomia
Baixar livros de Biologia Geral
Baixar livros de Ciência da Computação
Baixar livros de Ciência da Informação
Baixar livros de Ciência Política
Baixar livros de Ciências da Saúde
Baixar livros de Comunicação
Baixar livros do Conselho Nacional de Educação - CNE
Baixar livros de Defesa civil
Baixar livros de Direito
Baixar livros de Direitos humanos
Baixar livros de Economia
Baixar livros de Economia Doméstica
Baixar livros de Educação
Baixar livros de Educação - Trânsito
Baixar livros de Educação Física
Baixar livros de Engenharia Aeroespacial
Baixar livros de Farmácia
Baixar livros de Filosofia
Baixar livros de Física
Baixar livros de Geociências
Baixar livros de Geografia
Baixar livros de História
Baixar livros de Línguas
Baixar livros de Literatura
Baixar livros de Literatura de Cordel
Baixar livros de Literatura Infantil
Baixar livros de Matemática
Baixar livros de Medicina
Baixar livros de Medicina Veterinária
Baixar livros de Meio Ambiente
Baixar livros de Meteorologia
Baixar Monografias e TCC
Baixar livros Multidisciplinar
Baixar livros de Música
Baixar livros de Psicologia
Baixar livros de Química
Baixar livros de Saúde Coletiva
Baixar livros de Serviço Social
Baixar livros de Sociologia
Baixar livros de Teologia
Baixar livros de Trabalho
Baixar livros de Turismo