Download PDF
ads:
Rodrigo Silva Guedes
Secular Readings of Good and Evil in
R. L. Stevenson’s
Strange Case of Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde
Faculdade de Letras
Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais
Belo Horizonte
2007
ads:
Livros Grátis
http://www.livrosgratis.com.br
Milhares de livros grátis para download.
Secular Readings of Good and
Evil in R. L. Stevenson’s Strange
Case of Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde
by
Rodrigo Silva Guedes
Submitted to the Programa de Pós-Graduação em Le-
tras: Estudos Literários in partial fulfilment of the requi-
rements for the degree of Mestre em Letras: Estudos Li-
terários.
Area: Literatures in English
Thesis Advisor: Prof. Julio Cesar Jeha, PhD
Faculdade de Letras
Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais
Belo Horizonte
2007
ads:
T
o my famil
y
Guedes i
Acknowledgements
This work is the result of the encouragement and support of many people. First, I
would like to express my gratitude to my advisor, Julio Jeha, whose excellence and guidance
were fundamental from beginning to end in the Masters programme. I would also like to
thank Professor Sandra Goulart Almeida, with whom I have had the privilege of learning.
My appreciation also goes to my classmates and colleagues, whose comments helped me
enormously – Fátima, Eliza, Newton, and Erika.
I would like to say many thanks to my parents, Lucia and Kleber, as well as to my
brother Thiago. Their participation in this process could not have been better. I hope I have
made them proud. Thanks to my grannies, Ina (in memoriam) and Lília, for the inspiration
and the example to be truthful and hardworking; to my grandpas Raul (in memoriam) and
Walter; my uncle Walter and my cousin Thaísa; thanks are due to Édil and Flávia, for the
friendship and assistance; to Kate for caring and motivating me; to Myla, Lidiane, and Soha
for believing in me, too; and finally to all my friends whose wisdom helped me come out of
this endeavour with a feeling of accomplishment and an ever greater passion for art.
Guedes ii
My devil had been long caged, he came out roaring. I was con-
scious, even when I too the draught, of a more unbridled, a more
furious propensity to ill. It must have been this, I suppose, that
stirred in my soul that tempest of impatience with which I lis-
tened to the civilities of an unhappy victim.
R. L. Stevenson
Guedes iii
Abstract
Robert Louis Stevenson’s Strange Case of Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde dramatizes philoso-
phical debates over good and evil throwing light into the analysis of these concepts. By de-
picting opposite personalities in one character who, at times, behaves strictly morally and, at
others, utterly amorally the novel raises questions, first, as to how good and evil are repre-
sented, especially evil, in the figure of the double and the monster; second, the origins of
good and evil actions; and finally, the parameters used to define or categorize such actions.
Both personalities mark the conflict of reason and nature in guiding, motivating, and leading
men’s actions. The juxtaposition of the Kantian categorical imperative and the Nietzschean
Übermensch to Jekyll and Hyde allows an examination of how good actions are identified with
reason, translated by morality; and how evil actions are identified with nature, disclosed in
impulses and instinctive drives in the story. The Darwinian notion of natural selection is also
used in the analysis, providing an alternative and complementary way to look into good and
evil actions. This approach shows not only the way the literary piece discusses the problems
of defining actions from purely rational, natural, and circumstantial perspectives, by laying
bare criteria used here to define good and evil actions, but also how Stevenson’s book relates
to the historical context of Victorian culture.
Guedes iv
Resumo
A obra O Estranho Caso de Dr. Jekyll e Mr. Hyde, de Robert Louis Stevenson, dramatiza
debates filosóficos sobre o bem e o mal, iluminando a analise desses conceitos. Mostrando
personalidades contrastantes em um personagem, que ora se comporta com uma moral rigo-
rosa, ora sem qualquer moral, levanta questões relativas, primeiro, a como o bem e o mal são
representados, especialmente o mal, na figura do duplo e do monstro; segundo, à origem de
ações boas e más; e finalmente, aos parâmetros usados para definir ou categorizar tais ações.
As personalidades marcam o conflito entre razão e natureza ao guiar e motivar ações huma-
nas. A justaposição do imperativo categórico kantiano e do Übermensch nietzschiano a Jekyll e
Hyde permite analisar como ações boas são identificadas com a razão, traduzida pela
moralidade; e como ações más são identificadas com a natureza, revelada em impulsos e
instintos no romance. A noção darwinista de seleção natural tambem é usada na análise, ofe-
recendo uma visão alternativa e complementar no estudo de ações boas ou más. Essa abor-
dagem mostra não apenas como a obra de Stevenson discute o problema de definir ações
como boas ou más a partir de perspectivas puramente racionais, naturais e circunstanciais,
expondo os critérios levados em conta nas definições, mas também como o livro de Steven-
son está relacionado ao contexto histórico da cultura vitoriana.
Guedes v
Contents
1. Introduction........................................................................................................................................... 6
2. Historical Context of Morality.......................................................................................................... 13
2.1. Economic History and Its Consequences........................................................................... 13
2.2. Religion and Philosophy........................................................................................................ 16
2.3. Science and Morality .............................................................................................................. 22
3. Doubles and Monsters....................................................................................................................... 25
3.1. Doubles .................................................................................................................................... 25
3.2. Monsters................................................................................................................................... 33
4. Evil in Kant and Nietzsche............................................................................................................... 42
4.1. The Categorical Imperative and Jekyll................................................................................. 42
4.2. The Übermensch and Hyde ...................................................................................................... 52
5. Evolutionist Views on Evil ............................................................................................................... 61
6. Conclusion........................................................................................................................................... 69
7. Works Cited......................................................................................................................................... 73
Guedes 6
1. Introduction
Robert Louis Stevenson’s literary history is that of popularity amongst readers and
critics. In a study of the critical reception, Richard Dury compiles the criticism in a series of
quotes that address several aspects of Stevenson’s works, especially his popularity. Although
he begins as a modest essay writer, notoriety soon comes after the publication of Treasure
Island (1883), reaching its peak with the release of Strange Case of Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde (1886)
and other well received works such as Kidnapped (1886) and The Master of Ballantrae (1889) and
Catriona (1889).
1
His popularity increased considerably after Jekyll and Hyde, which quickly
entered pop culture in cartoons, psychological tag lines, and film adaptations that followed
his period (Linehan xi). In a headline of The Illustrated London News Dec. 221894: 769, his
death was announced: “He is gone, our Prince of storytellers – such a Prince, indeed, as his
own Florizel of Bohemia, with the insatiable taste for weird adventure, for diablerie, for a
strange mixture of metaphysics and romance” (Dury). His reputation in the world of fiction
is remarkable and the genres to which he is associated also suggest that: mystery, bogey story,
detective, and shilling shockers.
His popularity was associated to a growing literary market from which he benefited.
Stevenson lived off his writings and therefore had financial motivations to write. The market
at the time privileged the production of fictional texts in ways that kept readers interest.
Long works were often divided in instalments that were printed and released gradually. This
practice often required a style that was alluring enough to recapture the audience promptly. It
demanded that fiction was able to renew the great public excitement. This culminated in a
sensationalism that drove several writers at the time. Stevenson is thought to have been one
of them as he wrote Jekyll and Hyde. Although the book was short to follow the gradual
printing and releasing system, it was efficient in arresting attention.
1
From here onwards, Strange Case of Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde is referred to as Jekyll and Hyde.
Guedes 7
The context involving this book’s production also contributed to this sensationalist
effect. Stevenson says that the idea for the story come to him in a dream. In “A Chapter on
Dreams” for Scribner’s Magazine (January 1888), he writes, “I went on racking my brains for a
plot of any sort; and on the second night I dreamt the scene at the window, and a scene af-
terward split in two, in which Hyde, pursued for some crime, took the powder and under-
went the change in the presence of his pursuers” (Linehan 91). This association rendered
Stevenson with an aura of ingeniousness and mastery that influenced his readership. The
book was said to have been written in three days, although it actually took weeks until its
final version came out and it soon reached a popularity that outlived Stevenson.
Critics were of two minds about Stevenson’s style, according to Dury. Some frowned
at it, arguing that it was forced and artificial, referring to the absurdity and eerie situations
Stevenson describes in his books. E. M. Forster claimed he is full of mannerisms, self-
consciousness, sentimentality, and quaintness. George Orwell believed he was dull and did
not deserve the merit some authors attributed him. Others praised his techniques. His lan-
guage skills were acclaimed by the first two holders of chairs of English Literature at Oxford
and Cambridge universities, Sir Walter Raleigh and Sir Arthur Quiller-Couch. Rudyard
Kipling praised his talent for fine descriptions. Graham Green writes, “I think it was Steven-
son's method of describing action without adjectives or adverbs which taught me a good
deal.” Ítalo Clavino and Jorge Luis Borges include themselves in the long list of Stevenson’s
admirers. Vladimir Nabokov refers to Jekyll and Hyde as a phenomenon of style and uses
Stephen Gwynn’s words to explain his enchantment: the story “is a fable that lies nearer to
poetry than to ordinary prose fiction” (qtd in Stevenson 185).
Stevenson was outmoded and critics questioned his skills. This is reflected in his ex-
clusion from several books that dealt with English Literature, the Victorian era, and the
novel. Norton and Oxford anthologies kept him out for years. Only after William Veeder
and Gordon Hirsch edited a collection of essays in Dr Jekyll and Mr. Hyde after One Hundred
Years in 1988 critical interest was renewed. The establishment of biennial conferences in 2000
Guedes 8
and the implementation of the Journal of Stevenson Studies in 2002 reinforced Stevenson’s re-
turn to the critical arena. As a result, the criticism of Stevenson’s works is now vast. A series
of articles, essays and books, many of which listed in a website dedicated to Stevenson,
started reviewing his works, including Jekyll and Hyde. Carol Christ and Catherine Robson’s
eighth edition of the Norton Anthology of English Literature welcomes him back entering Jekyll
and Hyde’s full text with a two-page introduction.
The search for critical material on Jekyll and Hyde for the present thesis was compre-
hensive though unsatisfactory. The sources included the Internet Public Library (IPL) and
Voice of the Shuttle (VoS) websites, both specialized in literary criticism.
2
Capes’s Portal
Periódicos, the Muse Project, and Jstor were also consulted, in addition to the Scotland Na-
tional Library on-line and Google Scholar. The Victorian Web, the best reference for Victo-
rian matters on (and perhaps off) the Internet, and the Stevenson’s official website were also
checked. Most of them, especially the last one, provided information on the author of Jekyll
and Hyde, but little on the book. Most of the texts listed there were inaccessible. The Journal of
Stevenson Studies was also an alternative but it was also restricted.
Based on the titles the search aforementioned revealed, on a detailed critical edition
by Katherine Linehan and on acquired sources, it is possible to see that the approaches to
Jekyll and Hyde tend to concentrate on the use of the double. The double and the dichotomy
of good and evil in the narrative are explored as an allegory for man’s dual identity. Hyde is
analysed as a manifestation the unconscious or the ego in psychoanalytical studies.
3
Critics
analyse the book as an expression of the Gothic style, either in Hyde as a monster or the
setting of story as excessive and fearful.
4
The double is also explored as a metaphor for reli-
2
To make up for the scarcity of printed material in Brazilian libraries, an online search was done on
the websites mentioned, all of them recognized for their academic excellence. They can be found
here: <www.ipl.org>, <www.nls.uk/rlstevenson>, <vos.ucsb.edu>, <www.jstor.org>, <scholar.
google.com.br>, <www.periodicos.capes.gov.br>, <www.bartleby.com>, and <muse.jhu.edu>.
3
For insights into the question of the double in literature, in general, and in Jekyll and Hyde, in particu-
lar, see Miller’s Doubles: Studies in Literary History, Massey’s The Gaping Pig: Literature and Metamorphosis.
4
Refer to Dryden’s The Modern Gothic and Literary Doubles.
Guedes 9
gious divergence and moral instability. Recent approaches have associated Jekyll and Hyde
with evolutionary theories, exploring the topic of illicit behaviour as part of a natural proc-
ess.
5
Stevenson’s fascination for the figure of the double is undeniable and indeed renders
fertile readings of story within historical approaches. However, the topic of good and evil
remains an uncharted territory.
Although good and evil are easily recognized, they are hardly ever defined. In the
first place, leaders everywhere on the globe have brought these words back to common use
since the latest terrorist attacks, the war in Iraq and the conflicts in Palestine. It has been
spread all over to refer not only to terrorist attacks but also to gigantic catastrophes such as
the tsunami and the sweeping hurricanes in North America. In a smaller scale, they have
been applied to modes of behaviour in different cultures, places, and times. As a result, the
meaning of good and evil became quite blurred, varying from place to place according to
religious, political, natural, and cultural viewpoints. Moreover, if understanding good and evil
turned out to be a difficult task, setting the criteria to define it have become even more so.
Some critics claim we lack of vocabulary to discuss it.
6
Others still go on doing research on
the topic. Philosophy did its part in attempting to define evil. Nevertheless, philosophy was
not and should not be alone in this endeavour.
Although good and evil has been widely investigated in religion and philosophy, lit-
erary criticism is still legging behind. It has barely given any critical attention to their repre-
sentation in fiction. This thesis is an attempt to remedy that. Julio Jeha states that some
might not promptly see the relevance of studying good and evil in literature, once philosophy
and theology have apparently exhausted the topic. He argues that neither philosophers nor
5
Authors who have written about Stevenson’s works refer to evolutionary theories, but this could
only be verified in the majority of cases on book titles, table of contents, and abstracts. The texts
whose access was not restricted related evolution and Stevenson’s stories rather briefly. Some articles
such as Julia Reid’s “Stevenson, Romance, and Evolutionary Psychology” and Olena M. Turnbull’s
“Robert Louis Stevenson and Nineteenth-Century Theories of Evolution: Crossing the Boundaries
between Ideas and Art” seem to be more extensive on the debate, although this could not be verified.
Miller’s Doubles, on the other hand, is available but does not go deep into the topic.
6
See Neiman for a discussion on the lack of vocabulary to describe evil.
Guedes 10
theologians believe that they have said the last word on the issue. “From Alain Badiou and
Jean Baudrillard, to John Keke and Susan Neiman, from Terry Eagleton to John Feinberg,
from Adi Ophir to Russ Shafer-Landau, the list of contemporary scholars interested in evil
seems endless” (Jeha).
7
An on-line search at MLA database and Amazon limited to the pe-
riod of 2001 and 2005, says Jeha, will list over a thousand texts, including articles, magazines,
and books. Therefore, the topic is far from being exhausted, “certainly not for philosophers,
theologians, or literary scholars,” and dismissing it would have to be at one’s own risk.
Philosophy and fiction promote a prolific debate on good and evil. To be more spe-
cific, an interdisciplinary approach in the case of Stevenson’s work is coherent both because
Jekyll and Hyde reflects to some degree the philosophical issues of the time of its production,
and because it adds to these issues in its own artistic terms. It does not merely repeat what
philosophy has claimed about the topic but expands on it, including scientific issues that
enable other readings of the literary piece that have not been done yet.
Jekyll and Hyde tells the story of a doctor who attempts to separate his good side from
his evil side by means of a drug that he manipulates. The double character Jekyll-Hyde pre-
sents notions related to natural and moral behaviour that inform the understanding of the
story. This interpretation points to a long-standing concern with the origins of good and evil
and the attempts that have been made to categorize it as either natural or moral. In Steven-
son’s book, I claim, each personality of the protagonist represents either a Kantian or a
Nietzschean concept. Jekyll personifies Kant’s categorical imperative, the idea that a man
must act in such a way that his will can become a universal law; whereas Hyde embodies
Nietzsche’s Übermensch, the belief that a man must act according to his own will, regardless of
laws. In one case, morals distinguish good from evil actions and, in the other, nature does.
The contrast between Kant’s and Nietzsche’s views can illuminate the discussion on good
and evil as being natural or moral in its literary expression. Darwin can also be used to ana-
7
The arguments quoted here come from an e-mail by Julio Jeha, as he replied to questions relative to
the relevance of studying evil in literature when the project for the present thesis was evaluated.
Guedes 11
lyse how good and evil acquired different innuendos when contrasted with evolutionary
principles of natural selection.
The approximation suggested here between Jekyll and Kant as well as Hyde and
Nietzsche together with an evolutionist or a naturalist perspective, which begins with Darwin and
ends with Lyall Watson, was yet to be attempted. Parallels between Kant and Jekyll, Nietzsche
and Hyde and Darwin and Jekyll-Hyde remain an epistemological gap. This exploration is valid
inasmuch as it attempts to present another perspective from which to look at and analyse good
and evil in their literary expression the same way philosophy does it in and outside religion. Thus,
literary criticism can only benefit from this interaction with philosophy. Besides bridging a gap
between both fields of study, the present thesis may reveal a new apparatus for critical thinking
on good and evil in Jekyll and Hyde and possibly in other literary works.
Some historical elements are relevant to this approach because they indicate possible
sources of philosophical debates that helped in the understanding of good and evil actions.
They are organized in ways that indicate the connections between economic, political, and
social history and philosophical tendencies at the time. They are arranged in ways that put
religion and morality side by side with secular modes of thought that can be used to assess
good and evil actions in Jekyll and Hyde.
Economic, political, and social agendas introduce the discussion for showing, on the
one hand, the ideas of power, development, and superiority that the British Empire enjoyed;
on the other, they start the thesis because they reveal one of the main points symbolized in
the Jekyll-Hyde character, that of tension and conflict, generated by all the rapid changes
taking place in the Victorian period.
Religion and morality follow this historical contextualization because of their intri-
cate relationship with each other, the way thinkers questions them, and most importantly,
because they are parameters from which good and evil actions are defined. Then, the analysis
of doubles and monsters are added in the same line of inquiry. These metaphors are analysed
Guedes 12
as forms of evil representations and, as such, help identify how evil, and by contrast, good,
can be not only identified but defined by a set of criteria.
Guedes 13
2. Historical Context of Morality
2.1. Economic History and Its Consequences
The Victorian Age was marked by an outstanding scenario of change in all instances
of life, be they economic, technological, political, social, religious, scientific, philosophical, or
literary. The Industrial Revolution and its impact allowed England to become the fastest
growing country on the globe. The country, under the reign of Queen Victoria, which lasted
from 1832 to 1901, is said to have made more progress than any other nation has ever
achieved in so little time. The consequences of so much change were various, but some of
them epitomize this period.
Economically, England reached an unquestionable hegemony with its industrializa-
tion. It switched from an agriculture-based life and property ownership to trade and manu-
facturing. The cities rather than rural areas were the centre of the economy. The urban areas
became the site of commerce and growth. Having been the first to achieve such feat, Eng-
land saw its wealth increase enormously, especially with the development of the colonies and
the conquest of markets.
Technological improvement emphasized economic prosperity. One of the most
striking technological feats was the train, which “transformed England’s landscape, sup-
ported the growth of its commerce and shrank the distance between its cities” (Christ 1046).
The opening of the Liverpool and Manchester Railway in 1830 had a tremendous impact on
the transport of commodities and services due to the speed and efficiency it provided. Tech-
nology also signalled development in architecture. The opening of the Great Exhibition in
1851 displayed the power of industry in the “gigantic glass greenhouse, the Crystal Palace”
(1049), the size and style of which were meant to symbolize the unbelievable proportions of
England’s economic ventures. The economy, however, was not always constant in its course.
The economical development showed signs of decline and weakness towards the end
of the century. The long-lasting turn down that went from 1873 to 1896 caused disquieting
Guedes 14
effects, especially to the middle-class, which was challenged by a market that made a portion
of its products unaffordable. In addition, the competition of the Germans and Americans for
military supremacy contributed to this period of decay and frailty. Britain’s so far unthreat-
ened power came under dispute and the country entered the other side of its economic his-
tory, the side that revealed its maladies and tensions.
Industrialization defined not only economy and technology but also politics. Parlia-
ment redefined political structures with Reform Bills in 1832 and 1867. Conservative land-
owners participated in the political life of the country but manufacturers claimed for their
own participation too. In an attempt to avoid conflicts of interests and accommodate the
manufacturers, the Bill initially gave the lower middle class the right to vote. Later the work-
ing class was granted the same right, although women were excluded. The political power of
the middle-class in the Parliament increased in detriment of old power monopolies. Diversi-
fication of political forces governing the country consequently led to the capital of the em-
pire lacking a clear political identity. This political disorder was signalled by the vulnerability
to terrorist attacks on the part of the Continental anarchists and Irish Fenians. Government
Board offices, underground railways, Victoria Station were blown up, causing major political
crises. Therefore, on a political level, tension and incoherence were visible.
The fast-paced expansion of the British Empire also had enormous social conse-
quences. While the expansion of the empire seemed socially positive to rich citizens, bringing
wealth and pomposity to certain parts of the city with various palaces and luxurious buildings
on the one hand, on the other it proved negative. The population that was spread through-
out the countryside concentrated in the cities to work in factories and this movement from
the rural to urban areas happened too fast and caused problems. The unprecedented inflow
of people was too much for cities and towns to manage sustainable growth. As a result,
working conditions were a matter of concern. The long hours workers spent in their activi-
ties were extenuating. The low salaries were an obstacle to the high living costs and pushed
entire families to work, including children. The living conditions in the cities became ex-
Guedes 15
tremely poor. No sanitation system took care of animal, human, and industrial waste; there-
fore pollution was a constant problem. Health care became a serious issue. The filth in the
streets started a series of diseases that health care could not handle satisfactorily. Poverty
added up to dissatisfaction and agitation. The disparity between the lifestyle of the well off
and the impoverished became evident.
The Jekyll-Hyde character reflects this divide. Stevenson employs this metaphor to il-
lustrate tension, disorder, and conflict in economical, political, and social areas. It can be
argued that the conflicts seen in all these areas are analogous to Jekyll’s sense of self-division.
His character incorporates on several layers of interpretation the anxieties of an oscillating
economy, the political lack of control in the Empire and the social contrasts. Katherine
Linehan suggests that Jekyll mirrors the dissimilarities in “practice and preaching” (141) of
the Victorian morality, that is, the lack of correspondence between the way a man acts and
the way he is told to act on behalf of virtue, an argument defended by Judith R. Walkowitz
and Walter Houghton (qtd in Stevenson 141-49).
The Victorian man is commonly charged with a hypocritical moral behaviour. Ac-
cused of having “sacrificed sincerity to propriety” (146), in the words of Walter Houghton,
they feigned decency, passing off as incorruptible, while often living lewdly and licentiously.
This duplicity in character is said to be revealed in the public and private spheres of life in
which decorum belongs to the public and depravity to the private. Victorians hid their de-
sires and wishes to themselves and displayed correctness and respectability. The pressure of
morality was so excessive that escapism almost became justified. Despite having questionable
moral standards, these same standards were exported throughout the Empire.
The expansion of the Empire is also seen from a moral and religious perspective.
Morality is intrinsically interwoven with religious belief at the time. According to Carol T.
Christ, “many English people saw the expansion of the empire as a moral responsibility,
what Kipling termed ‘The White Man’s burden’” (1050). The belief that expansion is a moral
responsibility is related to an idea of bringing civilization. The Victorian’s sense of superiority
Guedes 16
somewhat blurred the definition of civilization. They put themselves in a superior position in
relation to those not as economically developed and saw them as uncivilized, savage and
primitive. Moreover, they believed it was a moral obligation to spread civilization. This is
when religion played its role. Missionaries were responsible for the dissemination of Christi-
anity in India, Asia, and Africa. Nonetheless, at the same time spread Christianity outside of
England, at home religious belief was increasingly debated.
2.2. Religion and Philosophy
Although this thesis aims to discuss the topic of evil from a non-religious perspec-
tive, one cannot help avoiding the historical role religion, more specifically Christianity,
played in defining it. Religious belief has had great influence over what was considered evil
and was involved in various degrees in major debates over the understanding of evil. Christi-
anity played its part in the nineteenth century and in the centuries before. This religious per-
spective is also beneficial because it help the reader to recognize the religious from the non-
religious.
The problem of evil, as it is commonly referred to, concerns evil’s own existence in a
world that God, the ultimate symbol of goodness, has created.
8
Evil is omnipresent though
not absolute and this makes little or no sense when one thinks of its origin. According to
religious belief, God is behind creation, and, as the sum of goodness and righteousness, He
cannot be the source of evil. Thus the question of where evil comes from raised other ques-
tions, the first being relative to why He allows evil to exist. Attempted answers range from
faithful to atheist ones. On the one hand, God is either evil, too, or not powerful enough to
eliminate it. On the other, God’s purpose in allowing evil in the world reflects His willing-
ness to let men follow their own path, and, as imperfect creatures, they chose evil.
Philosophy of religion presents a way out of this dilemma that supposedly preserves
the integrity of God’s image. Crudely, the philosophical explanation excuses Him from being
8
Refer to Mark’s The Problem of Evil: A Reader.
Guedes 17
evil or powerless and is intended to justify the origin of evil in men’s choice. Philosophy of
religion advocates that free will, the right to choose, solves this dilemma by placing the origin
of evil in men’s turning away from God. The fact that evil stems from the choice of not to
do good implies that evil has no nature or essence, but is merely absence of goodness or
God. In this sense, the problem of evil is clarified in the Christian tradition. An example of
this idea appears in Augustine of Hippo, one of the Church Fathers.
Augustine supports the claim that evil is attached to reason rather than nature be-
cause evil is a choice and does not lie in one’s nature. In City of God, he defines evil as a per-
version. For him, evil does not exist as an entity or in essence but is rather the absence of
goodness, “good may exist on its own but evil cannot” (474). Wherever good is not, there is
evil. Because God, the supreme good, created men, their nature could not be evil. “No na-
ture is contrary to God; but a perversion, being evil, is contrary to good” (474). Perversion or
evil actions only appear whenever one consciously chooses not to do good. Evil results from
the choice not to aspire to the supreme good, that is, God. Evil is the turning away from
Him. If the cause of evil lied in human nature, God would be to blame for such failure in
men as their creator. Nonetheless, God, as the supreme good, is blameless. Thus, the only
source for men’s wickedness is the turning towards themselves, away from Him. When men
prefer themselves to God, perversion takes place. Thus, for Augustine, reason determines an
evil action and not any type of nature.
Religious belief undergoes deep questioning from the mid-Victorian period onwards.
At this time, the Church of England was already divided into Low, Broad, and High Church.
The Low Church, also known as the Evangelicals, defended strict Christian morality and a
Puritanical code. Powerful in the beginning of the century, it shares this view with several
groups that do not belong to the Church of England, such as the Nonconformists, or Dis-
senters, which include Baptists, Methodists, Congregationalists, and other Protestant de-
nominations. The High Church, like the Catholic Church, teaches the importance of tradi-
tion, ritual, and authority. Some members of the High Church propagated their arguments in
Guedes 18
pamphlets or tracts, for which they were called “tractarians.” “Tractarians argued that the
church could maintain its power and authority only by resisting liberal tendencies and hold-
ing to its original traditions” (Christ 1050). These arguments consisted of a conservative at-
tempt to keep a superior ecclesiastical position before society. Unlike the previous sections
of the Church of England, the Broad Church takes the Bible not as a text to read literally but
metaphorically, that is, it should be interpreted in a sort of analogy between the empirical
facts of the world and God’s plans in which the first are signs or revelations of His divinity.
In this sense, this group is said to have a more liberal and inclusive character than the Low
and High churches.
One of the questions posed to religious belief arises from a philosophical rationalist
thought that had a long lasting effect in Victorian times. Rooted before the nineteenth cen-
tury in the philosophy of Jeremy Bentham and his disciple James Mill father of John Stuart
Mill, Utilitarianism undermines religion with the principle of utility. Utilitarianism says that
actions should be considered in their practical use; right and wrongdoing should be distin-
guished whether it promote happiness to others or not. If they do not bring happiness to the
greatest number, they cannot be considered effectively good. The objective is to examine
how effective actions are in promoting happiness to the majority. This is the utilitarian test
and “such test, when applied to long-established institutions like the Church of England, or
to religious belief in general, had disruptive effects Was religious belief useful for the needs
of a reasonable person?” (Abrams 923). Testing the institution of the church against such
principles brings controversy instead of harmony since a great number of people start to
think that the church does not pass this test.
The Church fails the utilitarian test for not proving its usefulness in promoting hap-
piness. To the Benthamites the answer to the question “was religious belief useful?” was
evidently no. One of the ideas associated to happiness at the time consisted of the fulfilment
of bodily pleasures, instinctive drives, natural impulses, and corporeal needs. This happiness
amounted to the response of sensorial perceptions, which many linked to an animal-like be-
Guedes 19
haviour. This sense of happiness was not encouraged by religion. In fact, it was – and is –
denied and condemned as sin. Thus, religion distanced itself from a practical reality in a
sense, at least for those who hold this notion of happiness.
John Stuart Mill strived to reintroduce the utilitarian principle as fundamental to mo-
rality. Resuming Bentham and the influence of his father, Mill states, “[A]ctions are right in
proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of
happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain,
and the privation of pleasure” (118). Believing that setting a principle of morality is necessary
and attainable by observing an individual’s actions and their connection with happiness, he
reinforces Utilitarianism or the Happiness Theory. Yet, he points out two major misconcep-
tions concerning its relation with pleasure. The first common misunderstanding is to oppose
the principle of utility to pleasure, as if the aim of this principle was not to achieve pleasure,
but practicality or usefulness. The second and more current misunderstanding is to assume
that pleasure is not worth an end to be pursued, as if it were not noble enough to be an ulti-
mate goal.
Mill emphasizes that utility is not opposed to pleasure; in fact, they commingle. For
him, “pleasure, and freedom from pain, are the only things desirable as ends; and all desirable
things […] are desirable either for the pleasure inherent in themselves, or as a means to the
promotion of pleasure and the prevention of pain” (118). Pleasure exists in things themselves
and in their use as a tool to promote pleasure. Things are pleasurable not only for their own
sake but also for the sake of others as much as these things can be used to spread pleasure.
Pleasure is an end, an ultimate goal. Nevertheless, whether pleasure is a noble goal depends
on the understanding of pleasure, or happiness, as merely sensorial or animal-like, according
to Mill. For him, the human idea of happiness goes beyond nature to a higher level: “few
human creatures would consent to be changed into any of the lower animals, for a promise
of the fullest allowance of a beast’s pleasures, […] a being of higher faculty requires more to
make him happy” (120). Against the conception of pleasure or happiness as simply condi-
Guedes 20
tioned to impulse satisfaction or bodily urges, which he calls content, he attributes to pleas-
ure a meaning that includes the enjoyment of the intellect, feelings, imagination, and moral
sentiments, which are higher in the sense that they are not shared by irrational creatures.
The concern with the necessity to establish a moral principle is enduring in Mill’s
work and it has strong roots in Kantian philosophy. Although Mill disagrees with Kant’s later
developments on the categorical imperative, he says that the Kantian “system of thought will
remain one of the landmarks in the history of philosophical speculation […]” (115). Such
adherence to moral values, or at least an attempt to adhere to moral values, is a noticeable
Victorian trace and Kant is still a reference when it comes to the debate of good and evil.
Kant is partly a product of the Enlightenment’s defence of reason or rationality in
that he privileges this faculty in men over others. Reason and rationality are prior to the
lesser parts of men, namely the natural. This rationalism, per se, enters the Victorian era to
be exercised as far as possible in detriment of the supposedly opposing issues regarding hu-
man nature. As morality is more connected to reason rather than to nature, one can under-
stand why morality receives so much attention at the time. Kant remains pivotal either for
those who call themselves Kantian for following the same line of thought or as a starting
point for discussing moral principles or even as a counter point for reassessing morality from
an opposite perspective, as Friedrich Nietzsche does.
Nietzsche refreshes the debate on morality with a reasoning that directly conflicts
with Kantian ideas. If religion is intrinsically tied up with morality and religion has already
been suffering from utilitarian criticism, Nietzsche contributes even more drastically to this
sufferance. His controversial view of religion, morality and especially the concepts of good
and evil shake the long-standing parameters to understand these elements. The seeds for his
discomforting ideas are planted in The Birth of Tragedy, released in 1872, in which he attacks
morality as Christianity defines it. He says,
[F]or in the eyes of morality (and particularly Christian morality, that is, ab-
solute morality) life must be seen as constantly and inevitably wicked, be-
Guedes 21
cause life is something essentially amoral. Hence, pressed down under this
weight of contempt and eternal No’s, life must finally be experienced as some-
thing not worth desiring, as something worthless. And what about morality it-
self? Isn’t morality a ‘desire for the denial of life’? (Nietzsche section 5)
Nietzsche ideally conceives life as an expression of one’s instincts, as the manifestation of
one’s nature and therefore, good. Contrary to this, Christianity sees life as evil exactly be-
cause it is natural or amoral. Under such light, nature and morality are contrasted to the point
of becoming almost mutually exclusive.
The Apollonian and Dionysian elements of the Greek tragedy incorporate such ideas
of nature and morality as opposing forces. On the one hand, there is the allusion to an ethi-
cal divinity Apollo, which is civilized, moderate, and self-conscientious. On the other, there
are the barbaric, excessive, and reckless characteristics attached to Dionysius. Both forces are
antithetical and are often in dispute. Zarathustra, a Dionysian, as Nietzsche says, elaborates
on these notions in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, and defines the Übermensch. Through the figure of
the Persian prophet Zarathustra, Nietzsche claims that God is dead, especially as a symbol of
goodness, lending such an attribute to the Übermensch. Having defined Nietzsche’s prospec-
tive of good, the questions of evil is the next obvious observation.
Nietzsche’s Beyond Good and Evil suggests an answer to the question of evil. Expand-
ing on the idea of morality and the purpose it serves, that is, power or the need to impose
control, he concludes that, roughly speaking, evil becomes the repression of one’s will. Be-
cause both Beyond Good and Evil and Jekyll and Hyde were published in the same year, the idea
that they can be paralleled in some aspects is not too far-fetched. Other connecting points
appear in On the Genealogy of Morals, where the origin of the terms good and evil is sought and
presented in relation to power. Nietzsche attacks Christianity in The Anti-Christ by claiming
its ideology is an attempt of self-empowerment and a disguise for exercising control. There-
fore, good and evil are no longer, in Nietzsche’s view, relative to following God, giving Him
Guedes 22
power. On the contrary, good and evil are relative to following one’s own self-created princi-
ples and values, and holding the power for one’s self.
2.3. Science and Morality
Scientifically, the impact of the discoveries in the natural sciences on religion and
morality appear even greater then the ones provoked by utilitarian and Nietzschean philoso-
phies. With The Origin of Species, Charles Darwin also causes controversy with his ideas on
natural selection or survival of the fittest and evolution. Darwin claims that through a strug-
gle for existence, creatures undergo a process he calls “natural selection,” which consists of
preserving favourable individual differences and variations that help them survive (63). This
means that any natural characteristic that improves the living conditions of a being is kept,
whereas any characteristic that does not contribute or mars better living conditions is elimi-
nated. The stages creatures go through during the process of natural selection define evolu-
tion.
Evolution in the Darwinian application of the term refers to the phenomenon
marked by biological variation that represents the development of a being, the passing from
one biological stage to the other. In The Descent of Man (1887), Darwin applies these principles
directly to man and concludes that men descend from lower animals, the monkeys, especially
given the structural similarities between them, and such association “raised more explicitly
the haunting question of our identification with the animal kingdom” (Christ 1052). Just the
fact that Darwin’s theory differed from religious accounts of evolution already caused great
discomfort. To admit the notions contained in the principle of natural selection or the sur-
vival of the fittest seemed contradictory, to say the least, to biblical teachings on the origins
of man. The fact man does not come into the world according to the literal biblical view of
creation but rather from primitive animal forms startled society, especially the pious. “Al-
though many English scientists were themselves men of strong religious convictions, the
impact of their scientific discoveries seemed consistently damaging to established faiths”
Guedes 23
(Abrams 924). People received the new findings with astonishment and soon recognized the
danger they represent to religion and morality.
The English philosopher Herbert Spencer applied the idea of evolution to ethics. He
disseminated the concept of “social evolution,” which compares the development of organ-
isms to the development of societies; he also discussed morality from an evolutionary per-
spective. Spencer anticipated the theory of natural selection in his work before the publica-
tion of The Origin of Species and coined the term “survival of the fittest.” In general, good for
Spencer consists in what contributes to the survival of an organism and allows its develop-
ment. He makes complex elaborations on this moral philosophy based on freedom and on
an innate moral sense. To put it simply, good or happiness, he says, is what comes from the
adaptation of an individual to its environment.
The application of the evolution theory to human thought had ramifications that re-
store the role of nature in the constitution of men’s identity. Stephen Jay Gould remarks that
evolutionary rationales, for instance, began to justify criminal behaviour (132). Based on the
morphology of human skulls, Cesare Lombroso’s theory of the delinquent man suggested
that crime is hereditary and that anatomical similarity to apes and lower animals stands as
evidence of that. Another example of the influence of the evolutionary thought in the ideas
developed at the time is the differentiation of social groups based on the analysis of brain
size. According to the characteristics of the brain, individuals were classed as belonging to
one group or another. Social Darwinism was also used to explain the inevitability of poverty,
since there would always be those who are less fit to survive in an economically driven world.
Thus, the evolution theory foregrounds nature, once overlooked by excessive rationalism, in
its role to characterize men’s behaviour and identity.
The questioning of religious belief by philosophy and science in the nineteenth cen-
tury is most conducive to a debate of new ways to understand morality. With the weakening
of the connection between religious and moral values, one is led to find alternative modes of
thinking to assess social behaviour, right, and wrongdoing, as well as good and evil actions.
Guedes 24
Conflicts between philosophical and scientific views and religion lead some people to associ-
ate science with evil because it distances individuals from God. Conversely, these same phi-
losophical and scientific views allow people to associate them to good because it brought
progress.
Literature reflected the debate on morality. The deep questioning of principles and
values practiced by Christianity is echoed in fiction. Fiction engaged in this discussion,
amongst others, in its own artistic terms. It readdressed philosophical issues as well as scien-
tific ones in detriment of the morality in vogue. It contributed to these issues in literary
forms, offered alternative and critical perspectives. Among the most famous nineteenth-
century stories that show these reworking of issues relative to morality are, for instance, Shel-
ley’s Frankenstein, which approaches the topic of evil by exploring the relations of religion,
science, and morality in the opposition between creator and creatures, allowing for a plethora
of readings. Along the same line, Wells’s Island of Dr. Moreau addresses evil by showing the
clash of nature and reason in experiments with human beasts. Stevenson’s Jekyll and Hyde
renders philosophical interpretations as to whether evil is natural or moral in the figures of
the dutiful doctor and his other dark, monstrous side.
Overall, the conflicts seen in economy and social and political upheaval during this
era, as well as the philosophical debates between nature and reason, are reflected in Jekyll and
Hyde by references in the duality of man’s character. The impact of the scientific discoveries
and the consequences of philosophical debates shook the foundations of society, generating
fear of change. This fear is represented as a metaphor in fictional monsters, which incorpo-
rate society’s anxiety of new concepts and beliefs.
Guedes 25
3. Doubles and Monsters
3.1. Doubles
The fictional context of Jekyll and Hyde involves the influences of the doppelganger
literature and the Scottish devil folklore. According to Karl Miller, there was a European
literary trend to search for new means to understand the self and its inherent duality, espe-
cially during the 1880s. Elicited by ambiguous social practices and psychological duplicity,
the double re-enters the literary milieu as a metaphor for the distinction between public and
private lives of Victorians, in addition to the contrast of opposing personalities.
Although the term double was translated into English from Jean Paul Richter’s late
eighteenth century novel Doppelgänger, its use goes a long way back in the history of literature,
without a specific work in which it first appeared. This difficulty to specify when the double
first appeared certainly has to do with the struggle that authors have to define it. Examples
come from Greek, French, German, American, and English literature in the classical milieu,
not to mention the many other literatures such as the Indian, African, Canadian, Latin-
American, which have been overlooked. The list of literary titles would be endless if the idea
here was to present them. Additionally, the variations in the use of the double were too
complex to pin down into one single application. Nonetheless, more important for this work
than making a list of titles or analysing the variations of the double is to show how wide-
spread this figure has become in the contexts of Stevenson’s Jekyll and Hyde. The point of this
section is not to go deep into the study of the double but to provide an overview of the topic
in literature to be able to work on one of the uses of the double in Stevenson’s work.
The word double suggests a few associations that illuminate its understanding. Ac-
cording to Carl Francis Keppler in The Second Self, one of the first ideas it brings into the
readers mind is that of duplication. The double can manifest itself either physically or psy-
chologically. Physically, the dualism may well be represented in double organs, mirror images,
photographs, statues, busts, and twinship in likeness, for instance, a twin sibling, or contrast-
Guedes 26
ingly as a monster, among other forms. According to Keppler, these are more recognizable
ones since they are more visible, revealing an immediate connection to their other half.
Psychologically, the twofoldness of the double might be slightly less obvious. One
identifiable clue is language. The expressions one uses in moments of distress are quite sug-
gestive. For instance, when a person says he was “out of his mind” or that “he was not him-
self,” that he was “possessed” or “beside himself,” he implies that someone else was there,
some other but himself. The singularity or wholeness of the individual is broken. Although
some consider these expressions a simple figure of speech used offhandedly, they carry the
notion of a double or a second-self and might be interpreted as a sign of such notion. Other
types of clue to the dual nature of men are, still according to Keppler, somnambulism, hyp-
notism, subconscious or projection of the unconscious, because they reveal, at least partly,
uncharted territory in one’s character and hidden parts of one’s personality (5). Therefore,
these two types of manifestation of the double, namely, physical and psychological, help to
identify it.
Major works on this topic include Sigmund Freud’s “The Uncanny” and Otto Rank’s
“The Double as Immortal Self,” which still stand among the most influential discussions on
this figure. Karl Miller also brings insights to the topic in his book entitled Doubles: A Study In
Literary History. From a psychoanalytical view, Freud addresses the double by explaining in
detail his definition of the uncanny and its origin. Initially Freud draws on the meaning of the
German root word heimlich and its opposite unheimlich to clarify where the uncanny comes
from. Among the several dictionary entries and examples that he lists, familiar and homely are
the recurrent descriptions that incorporate the main ideas of heimlich. Thus, it often signifies
what one is able to recognize and relate to on a close level. On the contrary, unheimlich con-
tains a negative connotation and is translated as strange and usually uncomfortable, uneasy or even
repulsive. Therefore, it often characterizes what is new and unpleasant. Uncanny appears to
encompass both German words to pass on the notion of something strangely familiar, that
is, something that is simultaneously new and unpleasant but intimately recognizable.
Guedes 27
The source of the uncanny remains arguable. Freud claims that the feeling of uncan-
niness has a different source from the one Jentsch believes it does. Jentsch advocates that it
is the intellectual uncertainty that causes the impression of uncanniness. He describes intel-
lectual uncertainty as the lack of orientation one has about his own environment: “the better
oriented in his environment a person is, the less readily will he get the impression of some-
thing uncanny” (154). This means that the more one knows where one is and becomes aware
of one’s context; the less likely it is for this person to consider something as uncanny.
The ego ignites the feeling of uncanniness. Freud postulates that, in its attempt to
deal with the external world and mediate internal affairs, the ego represses emotions. He
claims that the repression of emotions provokes a morbid anxiety, as he calls it. The double
relates to the uncanny inasmuch as the double represents this anxiety, this repressed content
inside, which the individual has chosen to hide from himself. In other words, the double
becomes this outward manifestation of the unconscious. It projects the latent content out-
side to a conscious level where it become intimately recognizable and at the same time new,
or strangely familiar – uncanny.
The use of the double in Stevenson’s work echoes Freud’s elaborations. Hyde can be
associated to the uncanny. Hiding is a form of repression and Jekyll admits that he has con-
cealed his pleasures; he confesses to having repressed an “imperious desire” to let pleasure
take over. The anxiety, caused by such extreme repression, acquires shape in the figure of
Hyde with the help of the potion Jekyll develops. Regarding the drug he has developed to
consummate the separation, he says, “It but shook the doors of the prisonhouse of my dis-
position; […] and the thing that was projected was Edward Hyde” (52). Hyde is the result of
Jekyll’s inability to avoid his will. Jekyll’s repression of his pleasure seeking nature is so strong
that he wants to separate it from reason.
The feeling of estrangement and familiarity typical of the uncanny is present when
Hyde is referred to. While Jekyll becomes Hyde, he feels “something in [his] sensations,
something incredibly new” (50). He is amazed at the result of the transformations he under-
Guedes 28
goes. About these transformations or “excursions” as he calls them, he avows, “When I
would come back from these excursions, I was often plunged into a kind of wonder at my
vicarious depravity” (53). Alternatively, “Henry Jekyll stood at times aghast before the acts of
Edward Hyde.” Jekyll’s feelings of estrangement towards Hyde could not be more intense.
Strangely enough and despite his astonishment, he also shows a sense of familiarity.
As he looks in the mirror, Jekyll recognizes Hyde as part of himself: a part for which he felt
“no repugnance, a lead of welcome.” For, as he eventually acknowledges, “This too, was
myself” (51). He recognizes the other part of his as “being inherently malign and villainous”
(53). At that point, Jekyll unveils Hyde for what he is: his double, his dark side better left
repressed.
Freud directly refers to Otto Rank’s ideas of the double. Rank claims, “Civilized man
does not act only upon the rational guidance of his intellectual ego nor is he driven blindly by
the mere elemental forces of his instinctual self” (62). Human actions conjure up both nature
and reason to form a worldview Rank called supernatural. Supernatural for him implies a
worldview that goes beyond the natural world to encompass the cultural world as well. Rank
identifies his concept of the supernatural with culture, which he defines as all that is non-
natural, or not belonging to nature, to put it simply.
To illustrate the notion of the supernatural, Rank compares primitive with modern
men. He points out that not only the primitive are governed by superstitious beliefs called
irrational life forces. In fact, both primitive and modern men share a spiritual self that is re-
vealed in superstitious beliefs. Modern men, however, attempt to deny superstitious belief
due to their pride on being rational. Nonetheless, they cannot escape it. This spiritual self of
modern men or civilized men is manifested in the spiritual values represented by religion,
philosophy, and psychology.
The cultivation of a spiritual side reveals an effort to overcome death. Rank believes
that men deny the biological self and create a magical worldview. They do so because this
worldview allows them not to avoid death but, more importantly, to fulfil their need to im-
Guedes 29
mortalize themselves (64). There must be a way for the individual to endure time and outdo
nature. By valuing the spiritual rather than the natural self, the individual should be able to
achieve such an ambition.
The fear of death and this attachment to the spirit lays the foundation of culture
(64). “Culture is derived from ‘cult’, not only linguistically, that is, as a continuous translation
of supernatural conceptions into rational terms” (84). Culture is understood as an ever-
changing process that rationalizes this supernatural worldview, demystifying the irrational
terms of this magical perspective and bringing them to the light of reason.
The double appears in this context because of a preoccupation with the self. The
double holds two interpretations, says Rank. The first interpretation is positive and associates
the double with the immortal soul. This association was recurrent throughout the ages and
usually evoked by the symbolism of a shadow or a reflection. The second interpretation is
negative and shows the double as a symbol of death.
Influenced by the Christian doctrine, the double came to represent immortality or
death. Rank postulates, “Originally conceived of as a guardian angel, assuring immortal sur-
vival to the self, the double eventually appears as precisely the opposite, a reminder of the
individual’s mortality” (76). He explains that the double is initially an identical self and a
promise of personal future survival, of eternal life. Later, the double becomes a symbol of
death. The double comes as an obstacle toward immortality, thus interpreted as something
bad, according to the author. It becomes an opponent and starts to appear “in the form of
evil” (82). Rank believes that these opposing interpretations of the double come from the
Christian assumption that the good ones deserve immortality whereas the bad do not.
Hyde represents the deathly. He embodies what takes Jekyll away from eternal life,
which is his pleasure-seeking side, his irrational self and his instincts and impulses. He per-
sonifies nature and its imperatives. As he wants to fulfil immediate needs more than to fol-
low reason, he cannot be granted immortality and is portrayed as a bad creature. The reli-
gious influence on this portrait is verifiable in the several references made to the Devil; for
Guedes 30
example: “if I ever read Satan’s signature upon a face” (17) and “my devil had long been
caged” (56). This accounts as the pivotal motivation for Jekyll to engage in the experiment to
separate himself from Hyde.
Separation is a form of denial. This attempt to exclude part of man’s identity symbol-
izes refusal. Karl Miller notices this fact in his investigations of the double. He refers to Ste-
venson’s work as “a project of separation” (209). He claims, “Jekyll is seen to use chemistry
to expel an animal nature” (211). Indeed, Hyde is referred to as an ape-like figure, a primitive
animal in some of his descriptions. Jekyll himself states his purpose in the will: “if each, I
told myself, could be housed in separate identities, […] the unjust might go his way, […] and
the just could walk steadfastly and securely on his upward path […] no longer exposed to
disgrace and penitence by the hands of this extraneous evil” (49). Jekyll longs to end the
struggle within him between his two conflictive parts by setting them apart, drawing a clear
line between good and evil.
The double and the issue of separation were in vogue in the nineteenth century fic-
tion. “Dualistic productions were becoming and established genre, indeed a mine of activity,
in the literatures of Scotland, England, and France, and in that of Russia, […] with Edin-
burgh and St. Petersburg the twin capital cities of the subject – the axis of international dual-
ity” (Miller 130). Rank’s examples of the double, then, do not strike as a surprise. He believes
that Dostoyevsky’s works seem of great use to illustrate the topic given the lengths to which
the Russian writer goes to explore the topic, especially in The Double: A Petersburg Poem (1946).
Poe’s “William Wilson,” and Stevenson’s Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde are illustrative too, according
to Rank. Although he does not go into a detailed analysis, he refers to these works as re-
markable concerning the double and separation.
Stevenson’s idea to use the double motif in the story raised questions as to the influ-
ence of other works over his own. As far as reception is concerned at the time, the writer,
reviewer and mythologist Andrew Lang suggested that the closest reference to Jekyll and Hyde
was Edgar Allan Poe’s “William Wilson” and Gautier’s “Le Chevalier Double.” Stevenson
Guedes 31
acknowledged his acquaintance with Poe’s “William Wilson” but was sorry to hear for the
first time about Gautier’s tale (Linehan 81). He probably learnt from the use Poe made of the
double to add later to the idea. According to Lang, Stevenson’s originality lies in adding a
moral sense to the story. Being authentic because it discusses morality may be a bold asser-
tion. Nevertheless, the impact that the discussion of morality has in the nineteen hundreds
does break ground. In one of Lang’s reviews, he writes that Stevenson’s story is a tragedy of
a body and a soul. The words body and soul should remind readers of the biological and
spiritual self that Rank discusses.
Other texts that also use the idea of the double in the plot are said to have had an ef-
fect on Stevenson’s writing. Katherine Linehan mentions Romans 7:20, “Now if I do that I
would not, it is no more I that do it, but sin that dwelleth in me” (49), to point out the rela-
tion between religious belief and the double. She also mentions the Edinburgh legend of
Deacon Brodie (1741-88), who was a master artisan during the day and, at night, became a
burglar. In addition, James Hogg’s The Private Memoir and Confessions of a Justified Sinner, which
tells the story of a man who is convinced to have been saved by Christ but is deceived by his
double, the devil himself, may have influenced Stevenson.
Scottish folklore alludes to the idea of the double in the figure of the Devil. Steven-
son’s own tales show how much of the devil figure can be seen in folk stories. Jenni Calder
believes that the recurrent appearance of the devil is relative to the author’s intention to
show how susceptible men are to him. According to her, Stevenson suggests that men are
naturally more vulnerable to the devil. Stories such as “Thrawn Janet” (1881), “The Body
Snatcher” (1884), “The Merry Men” (1882), and “Markheim” (1886) depict this inborn sus-
ceptibility or vulnerability to the devil. The last story seems the closest in meaning to Jekyll
and Hyde for pointing out the triumph of evil during a struggle with goodness, in the life of a
man possessed by an uncontrollable urge to kill. Calder says that Stevenson is addressing
what he called “the war in the members” (Linehan 127), referring to the conflicting parts that
constitute humans.
Guedes 32
The double can also be seen in Well’s The Island of Dr. Moreau. Dr Moreau’s experi-
ments involve the ethical issues of submitting animals to a treatment that educates them in
order to turn them into man-creatures, a mixture of human beings with animals. The unsuc-
cessful result of such experiments, with the animal’s side prevailing over the human, shows
the constant battles of men’s opposing sides, the natural, represented by the animals, and the
human, represented by the rational part in the animals.
Wilde’s The Picture of Dorian Gray depicts the double in an ever-changing image of the
protagonist Dorian. This image is a reflection of Dorian’s actions, which are committed to
pleasure and sin, all the impulses and desires commanded by his nature. Dorian acts as he
pleases regardless of a moral code that tells him to do otherwise. His image gets more and
more terrifying with his every misdeed, as if it were becoming a monster. Dorian yields to
temptation; he cannot resist it and manifests the passions within himself. This painting re-
veals the inner self of Dorian, the side that morality attempts to keep hidden. Thus, the battle
of nature and morality discloses the double in this story.
German Romanticism is remarkable for reviving the double. Goethe’s Faust stands
out as one of the most popular stories concerning the divide between body and soul, as well
as happiness and immortality in men. Russian literature, especially the writings of
Dostoyevsky, also recaptured the topic of the double in literature.
Overall, the double seems to be a strategy some nineteenth century writers, especially
Stevenson, find useful to address questions of the soul and immortality and, by consequence,
of matters relative to the body and death. Apparently, it helps to clarify deep psychoanalytic
issues, such as the expression of one’s most repressed feelings. In a more general sense, it also
serves as a tool that shapes and brings to the limelight the secrets and spoils of a second life.
Hyde’s manifestation provokes an introspection that makes one look back at one’s own iden-
tity and analyse it from a more fragmented perspective, since the unity is broken. Its actions
contribute to raise questions in a critical reader as to the foundations of moral standards at the
time and the origin of concepts such as good and evil in the life of the protagonist.
Guedes 33
3.2. Monsters
From Greek myths to contemporary stories, monsters keep on reappearing, often in
different shapes. They include aberrations, maniacs, vampires, animal-like characters, de-
formed images of humans and Satan as the utmost icon of evil. Monsters notably re-enter
the literary imagery of nineteenth century Britain. Although they have been portrayed nu-
merous times before then, they stand in the limelight of major works such as Stevenson’s
Jekyll and Hyde. Furthermore, their figures not only become recurrent but also ignite philoso-
phical and scientific debates within literature. The monster serves as a tool that brings forth
key issues concerning moral and natural behaviour, along with good and evil in Victorian
society. In fact, their popularity derives from the notorious topics they allude to.
The term “monster” renders some illuminating ideas as to its application. Leslie
Fielder, in Freaks: Myths and Images of the Secret Self, argues that the monster has been used to
describe “creations of artistic fantasy like Dracula, Mr. Hyde, the Wolf Man, King Kong […]
and Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein [sic]” (22). He associates monsters to literary characters and
reinforces that the term is “as old as English itself and remained the preferred name […]
from the time of Chaucer to that of Shakespeare and beyond” (20). Beyond Shakespeare up
until the time Stevenson at least, since both literary and theoretical texts still refer to such
entities as monsters.
The origin of the term “monster” suggests several possibilities of interpretation.
Charles T. Wolfe writes in Monsters and Philosophy that the Latin root of the word is “‘mon-
strum’, meaning a “divine portent, prodigy, i.e., something deemed as a premonition” (190).
Here monster signifies a warning from God. Yet, he quotes Fortunio Licet, who believes that
it is wrong to understand “monster” etymologically as a sign from God. Licet thinks that the
term “monster” comes from the fact that one points at it or “shows” it.
Monsters are qualified by the feelings they raise in an individual. Noël Carroll’s
elaborations on art-horror give a clearer view of monsters, especially the Jekyll-Hyde charac-
ter. These fictional beings are characterized by the emotion they give vent to, namely horror,
Guedes 34
as their names suggest. “Indeed, the genres of suspense, mystery and horror derive their very
names from the affects they are intended to promote […] the genre of horror takes its title
from the emotion it characteristically or rather ideally promotes; this emotion constitutes the
identifying mark of horror” (14). He defines art-horror as a genre of monster stories, mon-
sters that uncover nothing but horror, although not every monster in a story is bound to be
horrific.
Monsters often appear outside the horror genre. They raise other emotions such as
laughter, pity, sadness, empathy, for instance, and are often present in the children and travel
literature of fairy tales, epics, and odysseys. In such context, “the monster is an ordinary crea-
ture in an extraordinary world” (Carroll 16). The monster is taken for granted; it is a part of
the story that does not attempt to horrify. Horrific monsters must represent two key ele-
ments, namely, menace and impurity simultaneously. They cannot be only threatening be-
cause they would simply ignite fear. Likewise, if they are only impure, the emotion is more
like disgust (10).
Monsters are a menace when they challenge pre-existing orders. Monsters of the
horror genre violate cultural codes of behaviour and, for that reason, are often seen as enti-
ties that obliterate morality. This makes it possible to understand why monsters are “extraor-
dinary character[s] in our ordinary world” (16). They represent a clash of two realities, the
monstrous and the normal one. They constitute a disturbance of established ways of thinking
and acting, defying common knowledge and symbolizing danger in any social context. Mon-
sters not only constitute a physical threat for the strength they usually have but also cognitive
since they offhandedly break cultural rules.
Monsters are impure due to a difficulty to classify them. According to Carroll, “an
object or being is impure if it is categorically interstitial, categorically contradictory, incom-
plete, or formless” (32). Assuming that categorization is a way to bring the unknown to an
intelligible reality, the author states that monsters do not fit appropriately any categorization.
They remain inconceivable and unknown and are often ambiguous in the way they show
Guedes 35
themselves. Their impurity is also shown in their incompleteness or formlessness indicated
by the various disturbing shapes, texture, constitution, and smell they possess.
Monsters show this impurity in two ways. They shock one by mingling characteris-
tics of animate and inanimate things into their figure. Zombies, mummies, and humanoids
illustrate this combination of dead and alive. They also startle by mixing animalistic with hu-
man traits. Human-beasts, werewolves and the Jekyll-Hyde character foreground this mix-
ture. The Jekyll side symbolizes the human and Hyde symbolizes the animal side, acting
without the limits of reason.
The characteristics associated to monsters may well be seen in Hyde. In a conversa-
tion with Mr. Utterson, Enfield recalls his witnessing of the encounter of Hyde and the little
girl: “I saw two figures, one little man who was stumping along eastward at a good walk, and
the other a girl of maybe eight or ten who was running as hard as she was able down a cross
street” (9). Gradually leading the imagination to cause some anxiety and agitation, Mr Enfield
continues: “the two ran into one another naturally enough at the corner, and then came the
horrible part of the thing.” The element of fear, required in Carroll’s definition of the mon-
ster, plays a major role in the report: “he was perfectly cool […], but gave me one look, so
ugly that it brought out the sweat on me like running.” The suspense created in the narration
heightens the fearful and threatening feelings as the event unfolds.
Interstitiality characterizes Hyde, as he apparently is neither human nor non-human.
Categorical difficulties like that hinder the speech, making it difficult to find words to de-
scribe the interstitial. Enfield has trouble ascribing Hyde to any given category and resorts to
the neuter pronoun: “It wasn’t like a man, it was like some damned juggernaut” (9). Enfield’s
unsuccessful attempt to categorize Hyde appears again: “he is not easy to describe. There is
something wrong with his appearance.” Thus, Enfield’s perplexity as to what he sees indi-
cates interstitiality in Hyde.
Enfield also hints at impurity, formlessness, and incompleteness. “Something dis-
pleasing, something downright detestable. I never saw a man I so disliked, and yet I scarce
Guedes 36
know why. He must be deformed somewhere; he gives a strong feeling of deformity, al-
though I couldn’t specify the point” (11). “Displeasing” and “detestable” suggest repulsive-
ness, which is a reaction to impurity. The repetition of “deformed” and Enfield’s inability to
locate it or “specify the point” show the uncertainty about shape, size, or form: “He is an
extraordinary looking man, and yet I really can name nothing out of the way. No, Sir; I can
make no hand of it; I can’t describe him. And it’s not want of memory, for I declare I can see
him this moment” (12). Enfield’s insistence on trying to identify Hyde accurately shows how
unknown and inconceivable Hyde seems to him.
Utterson’s reactions also show the elements aforementioned, namely impurity and
threat. Impurity is evinced by the difficulty to conceive of Hyde’s figure and a strong physical
response from Utterson. He says, “there must be something else […] there is something
more if I could find a name for it […] the man seems hardy human! Something troglodytic
[…] if I ever read Satan’s signature upon a face, it is on that of your new friend” (17). The
repetition of “something” reveals this doubt regarding the looks of Hyde. The narrator says:
Mr. Hyde was pale and dwarfish, he gave an impression of deformity with-
out any nameable malformation, he had a displeasing smile, he had borne
himself to the lawyer with a sort of murderous mixture of timidity and bold-
ness […] but not all of these together could explain the hitherto unknown
disgust, loathing and fear with which Mr. Utterson regarded him. (17)
A sense of repulsiveness and disgust comes from Hyde’s impressions. Threat is signalled by
the fear Utterson feels in the room while he waits for Poole to fetch Jekyll: “he seemed to
read a menace in the flickering of the firelight on the polished cabinets and the uneasy start-
ing of the shadow on the roof” (18). The elements of impurity and threat follow one another
in the reactions of characters almost simultaneously.
The settings that remind readers of Hyde also translate impurity and threat. . The
space monsters occupy resembles the impact they cause. In one of Utterson’s searches for
Hyde, the narrator points out the mystery and fear the scenery invokes, “a great chocolate-
Guedes 37
coloured pall lowered over heaven, but the wind was continually charging and routing these
embattled vapours […] for a moment, the fog would be quite broken up, and a haggard shaft
of daylight would glance in between the swirling wreaths” (23). The dark and misty environ-
ment elicits the sense of danger and unfamiliarity. He goes on, “the dismal quarter of Soho
seen under these changing glimpses, with its muddy ways, ad slatternly passengers, and its
lamps […] seemed in the lawyer’s eyes, like the district of some city in a nightmare” (23).
Besides the impression of filth indicated by “muddy” and “slatternly,” the setting is described
as nightmarish, scary, and unreal to some extent. It is as if the place looked too frightening
and strange to be real. In this sense, the impurity associated to the monster contaminates his
surroundings.
Monsters can be associated to nature. Carroll refers to an animal side in monsters,
and Wolfe, in a historical overview of the topic, corroborates that by recalling the relation
monsters have with body malformations. Analysing Francis Bacon’s elaborations in Novum
Organum, Wolfe points out that, instead of omens as the Latin root monstrare implies, accord-
ing to Bacon, they are “an event which allows the naturalist to glimpse existing natural struc-
tures” (Wolfe 191). Monsters are anomalies, errors of nature being revealed. They represent
genetic malformation of foetuses, mysterious natural impediments to normal growth, varia-
tions, or deviations of an evolutionary pattern. According to Bacon, Wolfe says, they offer an
opportunity to look into one’s own natural constitution. However, monsters go beyond this
association with nature.
Monsters consist of symbolic representations created with a purpose. Leslie Fielder
argues that human malformations precede the creation of monsters: “men have always hewn
out of rock and painted on the walls of caves freaklike figures ever since art began, and these
have usually been considered idols or icons based on the human form but distorted for sym-
bolic purposes” (26). He thinks that freaks, or abnormal human bodies, generate the concept
of monsters, but do not constitute monsters by themselves. As he says, these natural varia-
Guedes 38
tions suffer symbolic distortions so as they can be considered monsters. Monsters are a later
development of anomalies, created or defined as such with a purpose.
The purposes monsters serve vary, but they are often connected to three main ideas:
freedom, pleasure, and power. This idea of freedom is based on acting naturally or following
one’s own nature, unafraid of remorse or punishment. Indeed, they usually behave indiffer-
ently to such feelings since they show no concern for others. Pity or the law does not restrain
them. Jeffrey Jerome Cohen says, “The monster is continually linked to forbidden practices”
(16). Any action limited by morality the monsters breaks: “Through the body of the monster
fantasies of aggression, domination, and inversion are allowed safe expression” (17). He re-
marks that monsters act as they please, regardless of rules. In this sense, the monster is free
and often represents pleasure.
Pleasure arises from the lack of limitations. There is no sense of denial when it
comes to bodily satisfaction. The monster is above the rules, willing to fulfil its needs. It
evokes “potent escapist fantasies” because they serve as an “egress from constraint” (Cohen
17). Through the monster, one is able to forget morality or any other cultural inhibitor. The
author believes that the monster unravels the pleasure of the body.
Like freedom and pleasure, power is a typical attribute of monsters. Carroll believes
that monsters in the horror genre are usually invested with some kind of intimidating power
or strength to subjugate or control the other. The political connotation attributed to them is
relative to the control they enjoy. “A tettering [sic] zombie or a severed hand would appear
incapable of mustering enough force to overpower a co-ordinated six-year-old. Nevertheless,
they are presented as unstoppable” (34). This depiction of power is remarkable of horrific
creatures and revealed in moments that barely make sense if one does not see them as myste-
riously powerful.
The notions of freedom, pleasure, and power involve Hyde more than Jekyll. Jekyll’s
maid recounts the murder of Sir Danvers Carew: Hyde suddenly “broke out in a great flame
of anger, stamping with his foot, brandishing the cane, and carrying on […] like a madman
Guedes 39
[…] Mr. Hyde broke out of all bounds and clubbed him to the earth” (22). Hyde sees no
limits to his actions and kills a person despite any moral code that forbids him to do so. He
acts freely and apparently with pleasure, the pleasure of doing it for no reason and no
bounds. Power is shown in his physical strength to destroy his victim without giving him the
slightest chance to fight back: “with ape-like fury, he was trampling his victim under foot,
and hailing down a storm of blows, under which the bones were audibly shattered and the
body jumped upon the roadway” (22). His fury is unmotivated and his violence is gratuitous,
as he purges his anger, unlike the proper and honourable Jekyll, who, as pillar of the Victo-
rian community, cannot vent his feelings freely.
Monsters also carry a deeper meaning relative to identity. They are linked to either
their natural side aforementioned or the cultural one. They can be “representations of other
cultures, generalized and demonized” (Cohen 15). The monster is a horrific stereotyped im-
age of others. It identifies and stigmatizes them with monstrous characteristics because one
of the purposes of the monster figure is to impose differences. They identify the other, either
negatively or positively, setting the boundaries between us and them. “[M]onsters symbolize
alterity and difference in extremis” (Carroll 19). They are an attempt to define the other and
consequently to define oneself, separating both radically. He goes further to assert that the
act of calling something a monster comes from strong feelings such as fear of contamination,
impurity, and loss of identity. Such fear must come from an assumption of purity or from an
unconvincing Victorian Puritanism.
Identity is a key issue in Jekyll and Hyde. The “Hyde” monster exits only until Jekyll
explains who Hyde is. From that moment on it ceases to exist because, according to Carroll,
he is no longer a complete stranger. In fact, he is part of someone who is rather well-know.
Monsters do not inspire any type of identification from the audience; they lack human char-
acteristics and resist explanation. The moment Jekyll tells the truth about Hyde in the will,
the monster is naturalized; it is brought into an acceptable frame of mind; it is made some-
what familiar and acknowledgeable, and allowed identification from readers.
Guedes 40
In this light, the monster cannot be seen as a double in Freudian terms. The mon-
ster must be a complete stranger in Carroll’s view; there is no sense of familiarity towards it
as Freud’s notion of uncanny implies. The monster is totally unknown whereas the uncanny
is not; hence, the incompatibility of these concepts of the monsters and the double in this
context. Therefore, Hyde can only be a monster until his identity is disclosed. Authors such
as Jeffrey Cohen, however, disagree by saying that the monster figure may work as a coun-
terpart of humans. Cohen hypothesizes that “the monster can function as an alter ego, as an
alluring projection of (an Other) self” (17). It becomes the exact opposite of the self.
Hyde’s monstrous image has religious, scientific, and artistic implications. This reli-
gious connotation comes from the thought that they have no soul. Katherine Linehan re-
marks that such image of Hyde might have led readers at the time to associate him with the
“Christian lore about the Devil, said to be cunning in his concealment of his bestialized
horns, tail, or cleft foot when he appeared in human form” (11). Linehan also observes that
depravity hinted on the surface image of villains and monster-men as well as the animal-like
appearance of Hyde could be interpreted a sign of “grotesque criminality or under-evolution,
according to neo-Darwinist theories” (12).
The Gothic style contributes to the portrayal of Hyde. Judith Halberstam defines the
Gothic as “the rhetorical style and narrative structure designed to produce fear and desire
within the reader” (128). She claims that artists, including writers, use the Gothic to evoke
the feelings of fear and desire. In her view, these feelings are usually ignited by an excess of
meaning, often comprised in the figure of the monster.
Later readings of the Gothic, such as that of Eve Sedgwick in The Coherence of Gothic
Conventions (1986), and Jeffrey Cohen in Monster Theory: Reading Culture (1996) based on the
Freudian unheimlich, understand the monster as the return of the repressed, the revival of
what has been buried inside human beings and considered foreign. These latter readings also
offer ways into the construction of the Hyde monster, whose traits and manifestation suggest
a resemblance with the Gothic. Other characteristics of the Gothic novel can be seen in Ste-
Guedes 41
venson’s book, according to Halberstam. She mentions, for instance, the typical exhibition of
a sinister mistrust of the not-said, the unspoken, the hidden and the silent. She also points
out that Gothic novels do not show the monster’s viewpoint and this is true in Jekyll and
Hyde, but not in others such as Frankenstein and Dracula.
This Gothic monstrous image of Hyde and its association with evil can also be cor-
roborated in philosophy, especially in that of Immanuel Kant, as is demonstrated in the fol-
lowing chapters. Julio Jeha remarks that monsters show the variety and the power of imagi-
nary evil creatures. He adds that they stand as a cultural metaphor and a literary artifice.
Thus, based on this line of thought, this work departs from this literary artifice to explore the
cultural metaphors Hyde incorporates, revealing their power and form.
Overall, monsters raise questions relative to fixed or established concepts and no-
tions such as that of identity in Victorian literature, especially in Stevenson’s work. Cohen
suggests that they “ask us how we perceive the world and how we have misrepresented what
we have attempted to place […] they ask us to re-evaluate our cultural assumptions […] they
ask us why we have created them” (20). He reminds the critical reader the risk of using crys-
tallized concepts, for example, unity in identity to perceive the world. This is one of the rea-
sons the monster comes in to existence in Jekyll and Hyde.
9
It points out to the reader the
human capacity to misunderstand and misjudge others with this practise of fitting the un-
known into fixed categories.
9
For further studies on the topic of monsters, refer to Jeha’s “Monsters and Monstrosities in Litera-
ture”; Gilmore’s Monsters: Evil Beings Mythical Beasts, and All Manners of Imaginary Terrors; Kearney’s
Strangers, Gods and Monsters: Interpreting Otherness; Kreuter’s Monsters and the Monstrous: Myths and Meta-
phors of Enduring Evil.
Guedes 42
4. Evil in Kant and Nietzsche
4.1. The Categorical Imperative and Jekyll
Kant formulated the “categorical imperative” as he tried to define moral behaviour
in terms of nature and reason. According to him, two natures constitute men. The first, sen-
sitive, is responsive to physical stimuli and allows one to know the world through one’s
senses; the second, intelligible, is associated with thinking and allows one to know the world
through reason. Likewise, two principles govern human actions, namely the principles of
self-love and morality. The former concerns all individuals’ search for happiness and the
latter concerns all individuals’ commitment to duty.
Happiness results from the fulfilment of biological needs. Whenever people follow
their natural inclinations and their impulses, they enjoy happiness. Pleasure is commonly asso-
ciated to it due to its sensorial connotation. Pleasure is a positive response to the human senses
of seeing, hearing, smelling, tasting, and feeling. It is the contentment derived from perception.
Happiness is inferior to what the philosopher calls true satisfaction, which acquires a transcen-
dental meaning involving more than the satisfaction of biological needs. The reason for this
inferiority is explained in the way he sees human nature and the action stemming from it.
Kant understands natural actions as based on causality. He believes that nature en-
genders people in an inescapable cause and consequence relationship in which all their ac-
tions are conditioned, that is to say, their actions are caused by a previous event, which in
turn is caused by another previous event ad infinitum. In this sense, actions turn out to be
irrational. Irrational beings are unable to break with this cause-and-consequence chain. How-
ever, as rational beings, men should be able to break this chain rather than being confined to
the impositions of nature. The happiness such actions bring are merely immediate needs of
the flesh, pure longings for sensorial experience. According to him, men should go after
higher satisfaction that originates in the breaking of such causal connection and takes a sub-
Guedes 43
ject to a transcendent state that is more rewarding for the soul. This happens only when one
is able to act from duty.
Duty defines an action based on reason and is the way to accomplish freedom. Kant
claims, “[A]n action from duty is to put aside entirely the influence of inclination and with it
every object of the will” (Practical 55). Acting from duty means to avoid nature and recognize
in reason the sole inspiration for one’s action. “[T]here is left for the will nothing that could
determine it except objectively by the law and subjectively pure respect for this practical law”
(Practical 56). Nature cannot have any influence on the decision to act. Reason only should have
such power to motivate an action. Acting from duty is to act for law out of pure choice and
not by any kind of imposition. Duty is the necessity to act from reason and respect for the law
(Practical 55), “for only law brings with it the concept of unconditional” (69). The law frees men
in the sense that it allows them to break with the conditioning inherent to natural behaviour
and with the relation of causality that binds one to the satisfaction of mere instinctive urges.
Kant reiterates that one may act from duty but also in conformity with it. The first
entails respect and a passion for the law whereas the latter involves the use of the law as a
means to an end. On the one hand, the law is an end in itself and represents reason, duty, and
morality, which is governed by the universally applicable principle, selflessness, and common
welfare. On the other, the law is a tool and is often misused. One misuses the law by taking
advantage of it for one’s own benefit, or more precisely, when following it is merely convenient
to fulfil a personal inclination. These are the foundations for the categorical imperative.
The categorical imperative tells you to act for the sake of the law, without considera-
tion for the consequences. In other words, people must respect rules of behaviour and not
follow their own natural inclinations. Thus, the common well-being is privileged over the
happiness of the individual. It is not enough to act in conformity with the law because one
might as well use it as a means to an end; one might possibly use it for one’s own benefit.
The categorical imperative says that an individual “ought never to act except in such a way
that [he] could also will that [his] maxim should become a universal law” (Practical 57). Good
Guedes 44
actions are “unegoistic,” in the sense that they aspire to promote common welfare instead of
the prosperity of the individual. For you to be good, you have to act in a way that makes the
principle that guided your action an absolute law. This is the core of the categorical imperative.
Overall, Kant not only points out a direct connection between nature and evil but also
establishes another direct connection between morality and goodness. Natural actions, defined
as the ones that follow one’s own inclinations, are evil in the way they disregard their conse-
quences to others as sociable beings and bring a lower type of happiness. Moral actions, de-
fined as the ones that come from duty, are good in the way they, first, free man from irrational-
ity and conditioning; second, show concern for others and their lives in society, and finally,
bring true satisfaction. Although Kant recognizes that men have both sides, the natural and the
rational, the categorical imperative leaves no room for the first and privileges the latter entirely.
Kant is criticized for holding an essentialist view of evil. Yet evil is absolute in the
sense that it reveals itself in all cultures; it is manifested, almost without exception, in all so-
cial practices and interactions. Nevertheless, evil may be characterized in many ways accord-
ing to the moral principles of each culture and social group (Jeha). One cannot deny that it
exists everywhere. However, it takes many forms and shapes depending on specific moral
codes, which in turn vary according to different times and places. Some critics distrust Kant’s
effort to blame human nature for causing evil; others attack the extreme moral attitude en-
forced by the categorical imperative as well as the attempt to universalize it.
Kant’s ideas on morality, good, and evil in light of the categorical imperative can be
used to analyze Jekyll and Hyde. Two major characters, Utterson and Jekyll, represent morality.
Utterson epitomises the law. His looks suggest the way people may see the law: a “man of a
rugged countenance that was never lighted by a smile; cold, scanty and embarrassed in dis-
course; backward in sentiment; lean, long, dusty, dreary, and yet somehow lovable” (7). Stur-
diness and endurance speak of Utterson’s lack of emotion and warmth as if he was unaf-
fected by it and suggest that he is detached from emotion but admired for this quality.
Guedes 45
Utterson enforces the moral perspective on the story. As an attorney, he represents
law and virtue: “In this character it was frequently his fortune to be the last reputable ac-
quaintance and the last good influence in the lives of down-going men” (7). He is highly
esteemed, honourable, and respectable – an exemplary figure. He stands for moral and al-
most religious correctness. His nature is unassuming: “It is the mark of a modest man to
accept his friendly circle ready made from the hands of opportunity; and that was the law-
yer’s way” (7). Self-contained, conscientious, moral, helpful, tolerant, and amicable are adjec-
tives that translate the ideas conveyed by Utterson’s description. Hence, the morally oriented
analysis he makes of the actions taking place.
Jekyll’s image is also that of a morally driven citizen. His association to morality be-
gins with the narrator’s description of his appearance. Like Utterson’s, his physical traits sug-
gest that he is a good man, “a large, well-made, smooth-faced man of fifty, with something
of a slyish cast perhaps, but every mark of capacity and kindness” (19). Outlining his fine
looks in a favourable light makes his morality visible or at least indicated. Other elements
such as Jekyll’s titles reinforce this association between this character and morality. When
Utterson checks his friend’s will, he lists the several titles granted Jekyll: Doctor of Medicine,
Doctor of Civil Law, Doctor of Laws, and Fellow of the Royal Society (13). The first two
titles show his training in medicine and law, the third is an honorary degree, and the last
shows how distinguished he was in his contributions to science. The reader is introduced to a
man of science and law whose profession and civil duty are beyond question and therefore
worthy of respect. Jekyll’s image vouches for moral principles and values. His actions also
strengthen his ethical qualities. He incorporates the qualities of a good man of the law; “he
was busy, he was much in the open air, he did good; his face seemed open and brighten, as if
with an inward consciousness of service” (29). Besides, there is an almost religious sense of
duty revealed in the satisfaction Jekyll apparently has in doing good to others.
Jekyll’s image is made even more convincing when one notices Utterson’s surprise to
see all the assets that belonged to Jekyll passing to Hyde in the will. Privileging an alleged
Guedes 46
murderer with one’s inheritance makes no sense at all to Utterson, unless he believes his
friend is being coerced in some inescapable way. The lawyer believes that, given his friend’s
moral concerns, Jekyll would not freely support a monster such as Hyde. Therefore, this
close connection between Jekyll and Hyde seems absurd, even appalling taking into account
Jekyll’s credentials. “I thought it was madness,” Utterson says (13). Fearing the circumstances
in which his friend Jekyll may be involved, he thinks about the bond between Jekyll and
Hyde and concludes, “Ay, it must be that; the ghost of some old sin, the cancer of some
concealed disgrace: punishment coming [. . .] years after memory has forgotten and self-love
condoned the fault” (19). The guilt of some irreparable mistake is perhaps being used against
his friend for evil purposes. The language he uses to describe the situation he imagines elicits
his religious values. He even checks himself for some wrongdoing in his past that he would
regret and suffer the consequences later. Yet he finds nothing and is reluctant to accept that
his friend may have done wrong and, filled with compassion, quickly blames Hyde. Utterson
wants to believe in the image of Jekyll, his friend, an ethical man. Hence, the image of an
honourable man stays unblemished.
Jekyll’s image is again linked to duty. Duty is, among other aspects, relative to doing
one’s work, acting on what is ethical or having moral and legal obligations. In the portrait he
paints of himself in the will, he refers to this commitment to duty. Jekyll starts his testament
by making a historical background of himself and is quick in highlighting duty to mark his
self-portrait: “I was born in the year 18 __ to a large fortune, endowed besides with excellent
parts, inclined by nature to industry and fond of the respect of the wise and good among my
fellow men, and thus, [. . .] with every guarantee of an honourable and distinguished future”
(47). This is the image of an admirable dutiful man. He even claims to have denied, con-
cealed an “imperious desire” (48) or pleasure on behalf of duty. Jekyll avoids acting on his
impulses and hides them for the sake of the law. He represses his natural inclinations to
serve a moral code as he alleges.
Guedes 47
This image of Jekyll seems coherent with Kant’s categorical imperative. In the figure
of Jekyll, duty plays a fundamental role in its construction as it does in the categorical im-
perative. Ethics is pivotal in his characterization inasmuch as the well-known Jekyll is pre-
sented as someone who privileges the law, the social bond, and the concern for others above
all. Dr. Jekyll epitomizes reason in his exercise of morality. His image is very close to the
Kantian ideal formulation. Nonetheless, Jekyll’s image is deceiving and its ethical hallmark is
unsustainable.
Jekyll provides several motives that testify to a doubtful personality. A careful inves-
tigation of his appearance unearths some hints that corrode his supposedly moral perfection.
Later in the story, “the rosy man [grows] pale; his flesh [falls] away; he [is] visibly balder and
older” (29). The gracious appearance that once educed his moral attitude now gives way to a
decadent phenotype that arouses suspicion of foul play, doubt, and fear. Jekyll’s servant
Poole corroborates this view: “[T]he man’s appearance amply bore out his words; his manner
was altered for the worse” (33). His external features reflect his moral corruption to the eyes
of characters and readers. In fact, early in the story, some descriptions signal a hidden cor-
ruption for example when he is described as having “something of a slyish cast perhaps.” His
attitude also endorses his crookedness.
The secrecy of his life as Jekyll is a hint to pretence. He is increasingly less accessible
to the public, to his friends and even to his assistants. Although he makes some appearances
that supposedly give evidence to his openness in the investigation Utterson carries out about
Hyde, he cannot keep them long enough to ensure his contribution. He swiftly surrenders to
the isolation of his laboratory, becoming a recluse. Whenever he is found and confronted with
questions about the murder case, he is evasive, keeping from Utterson any clue that would
involve him. Jekyll hides in the darkness of the night and more often in his other self, who is
aptly named Hyde. Another name would not make the existence of a secret more obvious.
Jekyll’s will is the most substantial piece of evidence of his unlawful behaviour. He
confesses to having done wrong, tempted by ambition, in carrying forth the idea to separate
Guedes 48
men’s two sides, “the temptation of a discovery so singular and profound, at last overcame
the suggestions of alarm” (50). He develops the drug that would eventually give vent to his
impulses, natural inclinations, or desires, but not as Jekyll, which would blemish the reputa-
tion behind this name. Jekyll cannot bear the guilt and sorrow that comes with it. He is not
prepared to take responsibility for unlawful, amoral, and egotistic deeds. Then, he becomes
the very self-centred Hyde, who pays no heed to feelings of guilt and sorrow or any sort of
pain for others.
Always unapologetic, Jekyll reports to a man of the law all that takes place, but does
not go to the police to unravel the crimes he has committed as Hyde. Although he may have
felt guilty for the consequences of Hyde’s actions, he does not excuse himself for carrying
out the research leading up to the commotion around him. Despite being aware of the un-
dignified actions Hyde would still be able to perform, he allows himself to take pleasure in
them. A dutiful man would feel obliged to turn himself in, but he goes unnoticed for as long
as possible and tries to ensure Hyde’s economic wellbeing through his testament.
Jekyll admits to having not found happiness being himself, as he confesses in the last
sentence of his will: “I bring the life of that unhappy Jekyll to an end” (62). His motivation is
the happiness Hyde grants him. “[T]here was something strange in my sensations,” Jekyll
says, “something incredibly new and, from its very novelty, incredibly sweet. I felt younger,
lighter, happier” (50). He enjoys the pleasures only Hyde can bring him through unbounded
physical experience. “[He] was conscious of a heedy recklessness, a current of disordered
sensual images running like a mill race in [his] fancy” (50). Hyde’s excess is Jekyll’s happiness.
Jekyll convinces himself of his dual character and the impossibility to rebuff it. He
also hopes to persuade Utterson to believe him and follow the terms in the testament. Speak-
ing of his other half, he claims, “This, too, was myself” (51). He accepts that he cannot be a
purely good man who has a passion for following the law. He is a mixture of such a man and
Hyde, who is pure evil. Conceding that “all human beings, as we meet them, are commingled
out of good and evil” (51), he explains that the duplicity in him and others is inexorable and
Guedes 49
not susceptible to resolution. Overall, Jekyll is inconsistent with the Kantian moral principle,
based on the evidence presented here. The ambiguity of his character elicited by his image,
attitude, and actions disagree with the categorical imperative.
To think of Jekyll in terms of the categorical imperative would be possible if one be-
lieved in a sincere attempt on his part to follow reason and morality for respect of the law. It
would be convincing to associate Jekyll’s actions to such concept if they were thoroughly
coherent and left no room for doubt that he solely behaves from duty. Some could consider
Jekyll’s behaviour innocent because they might see him as someone unable to realize in ad-
vance that denying his nature is pointless. Alternatively, some could perceive him as a hypo-
crite for betraying the laws in the most secretive way possible. No matter how well meaning
he may have been, his actions do not show honesty and candour. What the reader learns is
that he conforms to duty. He does not find the true satisfaction Kant refers to, as he does
not act for the sake of, or the pure respect for the law. Although Jekyll’s reputation speaks of
a reasonable person whose morals stand out and define him, eventually his nature overpow-
ers him. Jekyll relishes the happiness brought by the liberating effect of Hyde’s inclinations.
Moreover, both interpretations touch on a relatively bigger issue. More important than to
notice Jekyll’s hypocrisy or naiveté is to realize the hypocrisy of Victorian morality, which is
most conducive to Jekyll’s behaviour.
As many have pointed out, hypocrisy characterizes the Victorian era. Behind the
strong image of an ethical society lie the facts that contradict the image. Stevenson does not
refer to the hypocrisy of a “double-dealer” such as Jekyll, someone who is torn in two and
who at certain times behaves morally and, at other times, amorally. He is not concerned with
this rather evident trace of Jekyll. He refers to the view of men that ignores and denies hu-
man nature as if it were possible or desirable, but that begets a creature such as Hyde. This
view, of which the categorical imperative is an example, unravels an extreme emphasis on
rationality and morality that minimizes the role of nature in defining human identity and
Guedes 50
behaviour. It is based mostly on religious cultural belief, which often tries to abnegate the
biological constitution of human beings and its influence on human actions.
The pressure induced by society to be rational and moral motivates Jekyll to purify
himself from his nature, leading to his self-destruction. Feeling compelled to separate his two
sides, he attempts to get rid of his bad half so that the burden of sin or wrongdoing does not
fall on him. He is forbidden to show duplicity in character, although social practices bring
forth this duplicity. Morality becomes too constrictive to him: “I was the first who could
plod in the public eye with a load of genial respectability, and in a moment, like a schoolboy,
strip off these lending and spring headlong into the sea of liberty” (52). Feeling too inhibited
by laws, Jekyll craves for freedom from the social rule.
The result of this oppression is summarized in Hyde, an extreme opposite of ration-
alization and morality. Seen through the lenses of Kantian morality, Hyde is evil. He is the
consequence of Jekyll’s utmost fear to accept himself as a two-fold person. Hyde is every-
thing Jekyll tries to kill inside him, as the sound of his own name suggests. “Je” kill, means “I
kill,” or “kill” might also refer to what he wishes to do with himself, as in “kill me.” He is the
sum of all that is repressed by Jekyll and is never let show, as the name Hyde suggests, which,
in turn, hints at all that Victorian society would force its member to keep out of sight for the
common good.
The Victorian uneasiness over reason, nature, and identity foreshadows the existen-
tialist philosophy. Existentialism asks what “to be” means. This philosophy reassesses the
key concepts of essence and existence. José Ferrater Mora says that the term “existentialism”
has been overused to refer to many philosophical tendencies in which the premise “existence
precedes essence” appears.
10
For instance, Thomas Aquinas is thought to have been an exis-
tentialist because he understood essence as the intelligibility of existence; essence was exis-
tence made conceivable. However, to avoid the misconceptions of the various approaches
10
Although primary works of philosophy have been used so far in this thesis, existentialism is too
broad a topic and its main practitioners are too many to be covered here. Thus, for the sake of brev-
ity, an encyclopedia of philosophy will have to suffice.
Guedes 51
that have been made to existentialism, Mora advises to limit its applicability to a specific pe-
riod and philosophical trend. Hence, given the publication date of Jekyll and Hyde and the
philosophical trends that permeate it, the work of Søren Kierkegaard, the precursor of exis-
tentialist thought, becomes pertinent.
Kierkegaard, a religious nineteenth-century Danish philosopher, introduced existen-
tial philosophy – influenced by Socrates, Stoics, and the Augustinians – as a counterpoint to
Hegel’s speculative philosophy or dialectics. The foundation of existentialism, Mora says, lies
in the idea that no man is substance susceptible to objective determination; in fact, his being
is the process of his self-constitution (962). No external reality defines the self; such reality
does not impose an identity on man. Rather, to the existential way of thinking, a man is his
own reality and constitutes his own identity. Reality does not exist by itself or outside man.
Kierkegaard rejects the idea of determinism, which does not allow either change or choice.
The existentialist subject is not an object that merely reflects a reality outside him, but thinks
for himself and has the capacity to make his own choices.
Kierkegaard’s existentialism can illuminate Kant’s categorical imperative. The cate-
gorical imperative rejects the definition that nature imprints on the self; it resists this natural
objective determination of the self to embrace subjectivity. Subjectivity is an attempt at self-
determination and self-constitution. It presupposes that men can build their identity based
on reason and choice, that they can become themselves rationally and freely, independent
from an external reality that supposedly identifies them. In this manner, the categorical im-
perative makes sense existentially. Existentialism denies that objective truths determine iden-
tity. If one thinks of nature, or genetic heritage, as an objective truth, one cannot accept it as
a constitutive element of one’s identity. This denial exists within the concept of the categori-
cal imperative, which defines men through pure reason and excludes nature.
In Jekyll and Hyde, Jekyll’s initial motivation to split his good and evil sides, namely,
reason and nature, carries the existentialist view of man. Jekyll struggles to be someone who
defines and at times is defined by law and morality, without the interference of the irrational
Guedes 52
forces of his instincts and impulses. He endeavours to become the one to whom the cate-
gorical imperative can be applied, the supreme moral man and an existential subject. Never-
theless, his failure to do so culminates with the realization that objective truths may not de-
termine one’s identity but nor can they go unnoticed. Hyde may stand as evidence of such
realization.
4.2. The Übermensch and Hyde
Nietzsche writes about good and evil in direct response to Kant. Approaching the
same topic from opposite standpoints, they offer some insights that contribute to the analy-
sis of Jekyll and Hyde. These insights are relative to how good and evil can be discussed from
mainly two perspectives, one moral, the other amoral. Furthermore, Nietzsche’s perspective
brings to light other elements inherent to such debate: the ideas of freedom and the impor-
tance of power in understanding good and evil.
Human nature for Nietzsche is twofold; there are those who are strong and those
who are weak, and goodness is associated to the former, whereas evil is linked to the latter.
To be good, a man must be able to act freely, regardless of any restraint imposed by duty.
These are the qualities of a strong man. Evil actions are unnatural for Nietzsche; they go
against a strong man’s natural inclination. They characterize a weak man.
Nietzsche traces back the origins of the terms good and evil in an attempt to show
that the former reflects the assumptions of people in a powerful position in society whereas
the latter, by consequence, is associated with the less fortunate. According to him,
the judgment ‘good’ did not originate with those to whom goodness was
shown! Rather it was ‘the good’ themselves, that is to say, the noble, the
powerful, the high-stationed and high-minded, who felt and established
themselves and their actions as good, that is, of the first rank, in contradis-
tinction to all the low, low-minded, common and plebeian. (Genealogy 26)
Guedes 53
Both concepts exist relative to power relations and are established from the top down with
the purpose of maintaining power structures.
In Nietzsche’s reasoning, the term good was etymologically associated with the pow-
erful, the privileged, thus, with the strong. Conversely, the term “evil” was connected to the
plebeian, the ordinary, or else the weak. The main issue he addresses is that different morali-
ties and not a morality identify good actions and evil actions. Contrary to Kant, he believes
that there is no absolute morality, but at least two. The judgment of actions vary according to
the morality one inserts oneself in, since “one should ask rather precisely who is evil in the
sense of the morality of ressentiment. The answer, in all strictness, is: precisely the ‘good man’
of the other morality” (Genealogy 40). The morality of ressentiment represents the feelings of the
oppressed against the morality of the powerful. In this way, depending on the perspective
from which one judges an action, it may be simultaneously good and evil.
His view that the strong rules and the weak submit is present in the concepts of mas-
ter and slave moralities developed in Beyond Good and Evil. “The moral value-distinctions have
arisen either among a ruling order which was pleasurably conscious of its distinction from
the ruled – or among the ruled, the slaves and dependents of every degree” (195). Power
underlies the establishment of ideologies, a will to power being present in every individual.
“Where I found a living creature,” Nietzsche claims in Thus Spake Zarathustra, “there I found
the will to power” (137). Everyone nurtures a desire to exercise power over the other, “and
even in the will of the servant I found the will to be master. The will of the weaker persuades
it to serve the stronger; its will wants to be master over those weaker still” (138). There are
levels to power for individuals and they enjoy it according to their position in the social hier-
archies of power. Furthermore, this power relation is inescapable: “he who cannot obey him-
self will be commanded” (137). Those who cannot follow their own will, follow the will of
others. One will assume either the position of the strong or that of the weak.
In the Antichrist, Nietzsche answers the same key questions as to the concept of good
and evil in a very straightforward manner. To the question “What is good?” he replies,
Guedes 54
“Whatever augments the feeling of power, the will to power, power itself, in man” (22).
Strength is the ultimate motivation to one’s behaviour. He continues, “What is evil? – What-
ever springs from weakness” (22). He postulates that weakness can only lead to evil deeds
and goes as far as to connect this issue with happiness and poses “what is happiness? – The
feeling that power increases – that resistance is overcome” (22). This connection with happi-
ness is also fundamental in Kant’s reasoning on good and evil. Nietzsche cares to explain
what he means by happiness as much as Kant does. Nietzsche says it is “not contentment,
but more power” (22). Happiness for him is to relish power that comes following one’s in-
stincts without moral restraints, or else, free.
Freedom consists of being in a higher position where limitations cannot reach one.
Indeed, the freedom Nietzsche discusses amounts to not only being above limitations such
as morality, but also creating and implementing them at will. The strong are free because they
go beyond any assessment of values; they define them, they tell right from wrong and thus
submit the weak, those without freedom.
Culture is an obstacle to freedom: “the meaning of all culture is the reduction of the
beast of prey ‘man’ to a tame and civilized animal, a domestic animal” (Genealogy 42). It main-
tains order by repressing human instincts and desires and forcing them to live by codes, such
the religious. In his view, Christianity is an ideology set to make the weak seem strong, to
make evil seem good, to submit the disempowered to those with power. Interpreting Chris-
tian morality, he points out how some signs of weakness come disguised as strengths. For
instance, “impotence” is mistaken for “goodness of heart,” according to him; “anxious lone-
liness” is confounded with “humility”; “subjection” to God is taken for “obedience.” The
“inoffensiveness of the weak man,” or “cowardice,” as Nietzsche names it, is softened but
words such as “patience” are passed as virtue, and some men’s inability for revenge is trans-
formed into “forgiveness” (Genealogy 47). Not all these changes of terminology masquerade
the truth for Nietzsche, which is that the strong can be made weak; neither can the weak be
made strong by ideologies such as the Christian. Christianity, he says, stands as a remarkable
Guedes 55
example of “how ideals are made on earth” (46), how they are fabricated. He claims the same
goes for both concepts of good and evil.
Morality and religion are fabricated and contradict men’s nature. Appealing to ideas
of reality, Nietzsche proposes that these cultural ideologies are “purely fictitious” and have
no bearing on actuality. Concepts such as God, soul, ego, spirit, and free will, as well as sin,
salvation, grace, punishment, and forgiveness of sins are imaginary and go against the reality
that is men’s nature (Antichrist 31). Nature is real in the sense that it is not a result of creation
or invention. According to him, morality and religion falsify, cheapen, and deny nature.
Hence, the evil denomination attributed to nature. “Once the concept of ‘nature’ had been
opposed to the concept of ‘God,’ the word ‘natural’ necessarily took on the meaning of
‘abominable’ – the whole of that fictitious world has its sources in hatred of the natural (–
the real! –)” (31). The instinctive and impulsive characteristics that constitute human nature
acquired the sense of vice. Acting amorally, that is, naturally, becomes evil from a Christian
moral perspective.
Nietzsche believes that every man has an innocent side, that of the beast of prey.
This beast of prey must occasionally be freed in order to compensate for the repression that
culture and morality cause. He remarks, “once they [‘the good men’] go outside, where
Strange, Stranger is found, they are not much better than uncaged beasts of prey” (Genealogy
40). He compares the other personality that is manifested to a creature, a non-human entity.
He proceeds: “they savour a freedom from all social constraints,” that is, they ignore the
culture of morality; “they compensate themselves in the wilderness for the tension engen-
dered by protracted confinement and enclosure within the peace of society” (40). This crea-
ture’s actions represent liberation not only from social laws but also from the tension caused
by repression; “they go back to the innocent conscience of the beast of prey, as triumphant
monsters.” This personality is equalled to that of a monster, which could not care less about
moral bonds. “One cannot fail to see at the bottom of all these noble races the beast of prey,
[…] this hidden core needs to erupt from time to time, the animal has to get out again and
Guedes 56
go back to the wilderness.” This creature is described as an animal that must behave instinc-
tively, per se, naturally. He claims that men have inherent to their nature this uncontained
and reckless side that must be unleashed so that they vent their torments and channel the
anger. Only by giving way to this beast of prey or this “blond beast” does this torment in a
sense become bearable. These are the foundations for his concept of the Übermensch.
The Übermensch is an ideal man supposed to rise above morals and act on his own
terms, regardless of laws. As Mora remarks, he is not a historical celebrity, a hero, nor a bio-
logically superior man (747).The Übermensch is an ideal man and as such he leaves behind the
notions of respect for duty and acts above any morals. As Nietzsche requires in Thus Spoke
Zarathustra, “Overcome, you Higher Men, the petty virtues, the petty prudences, the sand-
grain discretion, the ant-swarm inanity, miserable ease, the ‘happiness of the greatest num-
ber’!” (298). Good actions are self-centred, uncontained, and carefree. For that reason, the
Übermensch, or the Higher Man, is mistaken for an evil man. Nietzsche says, “Man must grow
better and more ‘evil’ – thus do I teach. The most evil is necessary for the Superman’s best”
(Zarathustra 299). He points out that what the common man qualifies as evil is actually good
in the Übermensch reality.
Hyde typifies the Übermensch: monstrous, amoral, and strong. The first element refers
to his monstrous image. A friend of Mr. Utterson’s, Mr. Enfield, telling him about the epi-
sode with the girl who was trampled by Hyde, describes him: “There is something wrong
with his appearance; something displeasing, something downright detestable […] He must be
deformed somewhere; he gives a strong feeling of deformity, although I couldn’t specify the
point” (11). Hyde is presented as animal-like, a frightening creature. Indeed, the slight sug-
gestions of character but mostly physical deformity at the time were enough to cause great
impact in the imaginary of Stevenson’s readers, according to Linehan. She notes (as afore-
mentioned) that they might have raised associations such as the “Christian lore about the
Devil, said to be cunning in his concealment of his bestialized horns, tail or cleft foot when
he appeared in human form; […] neo-Darwinist theories interpreting animal-like features in
Guedes 57
humans as signs of grotesque criminality or under-evolution” (11). The beastly shape that
Hyde’s body conceals also resembles Nietzsche’s image of the best of prey, Strange monster
he claims to live inside human beings imprisoned by social rules and practices. This associa-
tion is reinforced by a second element in Hyde’s personality, or to be more precise, his ac-
tions.
The second element that characterizes the Übermensch is acting naturally. In this case,
acting naturally does not mean following a habit or doing as usual, but rather following one’s
own nature. Instead of following reason the way the reputable Dr. Jekyll does, Hyde lets out
his nature, instincts, or impulses. This is suggested in the letter Jekyll addresses to his friend
Lanyon, asking him a favour, and saying that if he fails to do it, that will be the shipwreck of
his reason. Reason here is endangered because Hyde, the natural side, is taking over Jekyll.
Jekyll confesses what Hyde embodies. From the memories of his transformations and ex-
periences through which he, as Hyde, undergoes, he concludes that to be Jekyll “was to die
to those appetites which I had long secretly indulged” (55). These appetites amount to bodily
pleasures. Hyde cannot be dissociated from the earthly and mundane. Purely material, all that
appeals to the flesh and to the senses characterize Hyde. He lives under nature’s command
and is devoid of unnatural qualities such as spirit or morals.
Hyde acts amorally and regardless of laws. Similarly to Nietzschean Übermensch, Hyde
behaves as if an innocent creature, showing no knowledge or care for rules and the conse-
quences that breaking them may bring. The case of Sir Danvers Carew shows Hyde follow-
ing his impulses and beating a man to death gratuitously: “[Hyde] clubbed him [Carew] to the
earth, […] with ape-like fury, he was trampling his victim under foot, and hailing down a
storm of blows, under which the bones were audibly shattered and the body jumped upon
the roadway” (22). He has no reason to kill but still he goes on merciless as a reckless mur-
derer. These strong impulses that cause him to act on his will with no respect for laws have
to do with another element that constitutes the notion of the Übermensch: power.
Guedes 58
Power or strength is the ultimate element that defines the Übermensch. It characterizes
him, according to Nietzsche, and is related to a sense of control over others and a sense
freedom from any kind of moral imposition. In a passage where Utterson is about to find
out the secret Jekyll hides in a letter by Lanyon, Hyde says, “If you [Lanyon] shall prefer a
new province of knowledge and new avenues to fame and power shall be laid open to you,
here, in this room, upon the instant; and your sight shall be blasted by a prodigy to stagger
the unbelief of Satan” (46). The “will to power,” as Nietzsche writes, motivates the charac-
ter’s actions. In this sense, Hyde is the personification of the overman because he enjoys
power as a strong and good creature.
Although Hyde is depicted as an evil creature in the story, he can be understood as a
good man in Nietzschean terms. Good is not connected to justice or pity in the philoso-
pher’s view. Contrary to what some may argue, good is relative to being powerful and strong,
to being superior, or above the laws as Hyde is. Moreover, it is not even a question of being,
because for Nietzsche there is no being, but only doing: “popular morality also separates
strength from expressions of strength, as if there were a neutral substratum behind the
strong man, which was free to express strength or not to do so. But there is no such substra-
tum; there is no ‘being’ behind doing, […] the deed is everything” (Genealogy 45). Actions,
then, define a man. Thus, Hyde’s actions define him as good in Nietzschean terms. He in-
corporates the three main elements that identify the ideal man Nietzsche creates, namely, the
monstrous appeal, the amoral behaviour, and the urge for power. In those three elements,
Hyde can be said to resemble the Übermensch.
A rather extreme individualistic idea hides behind the concept of the Übermensch. As
aforementioned, the Übermensch is idiosyncratically self-centred and his relationship with the
other is that of indifference. He concentrates on the self, unlike what Kant dictates in the
categorical imperative that teaches selflessness and collectivism. This individualistic trace is
evident in Hyde. The narrator says, “Jekyll had more than a father’s interest,” whereas “Hyde
had more than a son’s indifference” (55). Jekyll is portrayed as someone who has company, a
Guedes 59
sociable figure as he preferred [to be] the elderly and the discontented doctor, surrounded by
friends” (55). However, Hyde is friendless and most often despised by those who see him, as
Jekyll observes. This individualism is built on the image of a man who isolates himself and
keeps no unnecessary connections.
Other parallels with Kant can be drawn in the debate of moral and amoral actions.
Nietzsche attacks Kant by claiming that morality is destructive rather than protective. The
selflessness and collectivism Kant defends does not preserve men. On the contrary, it en-
dangers life: “What destroys a man more quickly than to work, think and feel without inner
necessity, without any deep personal desire, without pleasure – as a mere automaton of duty?
That is the recipe for decadence, and no less for idiocy” (Antichrist 28). Nietzsche points out
how Kant empties the idea of the self, the person, the man, in favour of social homogeneity,
equality, and universality. Nietzsche says that this impersonation can only make unattainable
the concepts Kant refers to, namely “virtue,” “duty,” and “good for its own”; “goodness
grounded upon impersonality or a notion of universal validity – these are all chimeras, and in
them one finds only an expression of the decay, the last collapse of life […] Quite the con-
trary is demanded [. . .] that every man find his own virtue, his own categorical imperative”
(28). Nietzsche believes that the self, for its own sake, must protect itself and lead its own life
so that goodness, as he understands it, becomes real and possible, not only a dream.
This conflict permeates Jekyll and Hyde’s existence. Jekyll’s commitment to duty and
the others around him is often counterbalanced by Hyde’s commitment to his nature and
himself. While the first attempts to cling to this moral bonds that turn men into equals, the
latter carelessly overlooks them to indulge in egoistic deeds. Consequently, one loses refer-
ence to understand vices and virtues, good and evil; one either has society as a whole to
judge one’s actions or the self to do so; one departs from either morality or nature to assess
one’s actions. As the story suggests with the supposed death of Henry Jekyll, the self’s point of
reference, the natural is established more strongly, gaining more attention and acceptability.
Guedes 60
Although Nietzsche seems thoroughly coherent, he presents a contradictory view of
men. While he claims that there is no essence to a strong man, no being behind the deed, he
introduces a determinist perspective to discuss men and their relation with power. “Mankind
surely does not represent an evolution toward a better or stronger or higher level, as progress
is now understood. This ‘progress’ is merely a modern idea, which is to say, a false idea [. . .]
the process of evolution does not necessarily mean elevation, enhancement, strengthening”
(23). He believes that the strong man or the higher man appears by accident when uncovered
by the heavy layers of the Christian religious ideology. One is born strong or weak and there
is no becoming. As he says, “[W]e weak ones are, after all, weak; it would be good if we did
nothing for which we are not strong enough” (Genealogy 46). Men cannot choose to be strong
and therefore powerful. He explains that life appears to man “as an instinct of growth, for
survival, for the accumulation of forces, for power” (Antichrist 24). Recalling Darwin’s theory
of evolution and natural selection, Nietzsche argues that men cannot deny their instinct to
self-preservation by having moral values govern their lives.
Guedes 61
5. Evolutionist Views on Evil
The theory of evolution renders interpretations of the principles of natural selection
in the literary field that add to the view of good and evil in Jekyll and Hyde. Patricia Cohen
remarks in an article for the New York Times, “Darwin’s scientific theories about the evolu-
tion of species can be applied to today’s patterns of human behaviour” She analyses the in-
fluence of Darwinism in a political sphere, pointing out how it is used to by conservative
thinkers. She quotes Karl Marx, who wrote that “Darwin’s book is very important and serves
me as a basis in natural science for the class struggle in history.” Darwinism crosses the
boundaries of biology and the natural sciences to enter political and economical grounds.
The significance of the theory of evolution is noticeable in other fields of study such
as sociology and philosophy. Herbert Spencer, for instance, was one of the authors that initi-
ated this practice by introducing the analogous “social evolution.” He explained that mem-
bers of a group occupy powerful positions in stratified society because they are more fit than
others. They fill the requirements of their rank in a social hierarchy. In this case, poverty and
social inequality are justified in evolutionary terms by lack of adjustment or appropriate char-
acteristics. Francis Galton promoted the eugenic social philosophy that supports the im-
provement of hereditary characteristics through selective breeding. According to him, supe-
rior or fit members of society instead of inferior and unfit should be used to enhance human
constitution. The social implications of this line of thought include racism and segregation.
Darwin’s Origin of Species consolidates the principles of natural selection, which are
extended to apply to human beings in The Descent of Men. The theory of evolution based on
these principles affected the way Victorians understood men’s origin, their relationship with
each other and with their environment. It interfered in traditional views and shook long-
standing beliefs mainly attached to religion, touching upon the question of moral actions and
natural behaviour. Darwinism has been retaken as a parameter for criticism in other fields of
knowledge. Likewise, it can be used as a parameter in literature, especially in Jekyll and Hyde.
Guedes 62
In an approach that brings together literature and Darwinism,
the key elements of the theory
of evolution can be juxtaposed to the analysis of the Jekyll-Hyde character in order to ex-
pand it on a more socio-philosophical level.
11
Evolution is based on the principles of natural selection. The term evolution derives
from the Latin word evolvere and literally means to roll out, roll open, or unfold. In the Dar-
winian view, evolution refers to stages of development that all species go through. It defines
the process of transformation that plants and animals endure every generation, moving them
from lower and simpler biological systems to higher and more complex ones. It describes the
natural advancements taking place in organisms, which increases their fitness for survival.
According to Darwin, this process is essentially fortuitous.
Evolution is based on chance. This aspect must be clear so that one can understand
in which way the environment participates in the process and avoid the Lamarckian belief
that the environment actually changes organisms. Darwin postulated that the individual of
any given species will adapt or not to the situations found in the environment. The environ-
ment in turn has no direct interference in the inheritance of their biological make up, that is,
it does not modify structures in animals and plants to make them more adjusted. Simply,
those less fit to survive are slowly but inexorably replaced by those more better- adapted.
Evolution implies that these characteristics are not simply given, but attained by
struggle and competition amongst other living creatures. “As more individuals are born than
can possibly survive, there must in every case be a struggle for existence, either one individ-
ual with another of the same species, or with the individuals of distinct species, or with the
physical conditions of life” (Darwin 50). Self-preservation depends on the ability to compete
for survival.
The evolution of a species is considered not only on its own, but in relation to oth-
ers. Darwin discusses evolution from a collective standpoint that takes into account species
living together in community instead of individually. This accounts for the way one should
11
For more information on Darwin and literature, refer to Joseph Carroll’s Literary Darwinism.
Guedes 63
analyse a case from an evolutionary standpoint. It tells one not to overlook the aspects that
only a collective perspective allows one to see. These aspects are relative to understanding
creatures and men, not in isolation, but in the relationship established between themselves
and their surroundings.
Three main criteria can be observed in the evolutionary process. The first describes a
struggle for survival, and the attempt to guarantee the preservation and continuity of legacy.
The second entails men’s adaptation to the environment and the capacity to adjust to their
surroundings. Finally, the third comprises the development towards more complex biological
structures; the passage from lower to higher forms. Darwin reiterates that not only natural
features are passed on every generation, but also the ability to use moral faculties.
These criteria can be used to analyze the Jekyll-Hyde character on a social level.
Jekyll then would be a figure struggling for survival. He can be seen as someone who does
not adapt to his environment. Belonging to a high rank in the social hierarchy, he fails to
comply with the obligations ascribed to someone in such position: impeccable moral conduct
and flawless character. He is part of a group, the noble and supposedly decent citizens, that
imposes on him a highly strict ethical posture. Although he strives to maintain such posture
for the sake of status and merit, he fails. His public life elicits his compatibility with a morally
geared up environment. However, his private life dramatically contrasts his public one.
Jekyll’s preference for his private life endorses his inability to cope with his surroundings,
background, and rank.
Although Jekyll apparently survives, he strives to keep his other side, Hyde, from
perishing. Before he suspects losing control of his experiments, he is careful enough to en-
sure his continuing existence through Hyde by means of a will. Although he initially does not
make it clear that Hyde and him are the same person, he makes sure that if anything goes
wrong in the course of events, Hyde will be endowed with economic conditions to support
himself. Hyde “should step into the said Henry Jekyll’s shoes without further delay and free
from any burden or obligation” (13). His efforts are towards continuity. Later, when he is
Guedes 64
sure of his end but unsure of his existence as Hyde, he restates his case justifying the terms in
the will. By explaining what he had previously kept from Utterson, he expects to persuade
his friend to execute his requests out of sympathy. In this way, he convinces himself that
Hyde will continue to exist. Jekyll’s testament is compelling evidence of his attempt to survive.
The last Darwinian criterion refers to Jekyll’s development. Instead of reaching a
more complex level of social life, Jekyll degenerates. He undergoes a process of involution
that unravels his most animal-like characteristics in the figure of Hyde. These animalistic
characteristics can be seen both physically and psychologically. While Hyde victimizes the
child, his fury is referred to as “ape-like” (22). Like the narrator, Poole has the impression
that Hyde looks like a monkey by the way he jumps and makes noises in the laboratory (37-
38). Hyde is often framed as a raging beast trapped inside Jekyll (61). These characteristics
are usually referred to as a sign of lower life forms and primitiveness, given their irrational
and sensorial peculiarities. Being Hyde means to regress from complexity and fitness. Hyde is
shown as unfit, inept, and ineligible for life in society.
A socio-evolutionist view of Jekyll and Hyde generates a circumstantial understanding
of what Kant and Nietzsche proposed as good and evil. From such perspective, good and
evil lose their moral meanings and turn into better or worse adaptation to the environment.
Good actions can be correlated with the environmental adaptive effort, according to which a
person (in fact, any living being) is better if he adjusts to his milieu. A person is worse off if
he is unfit for the environment. Jekyll then would be seen as struggling for survival in his at-
tempt to escape the stifling stricture of his social environment, whereas Hyde would be seen as
a rugged individual, ill adapted to existence in society and more fit for survival in wild nature.
This view slightly redirects the focus of attention from reason and nature as the
sources of good and evil to include the importance of the environment. Although it does not
exclude either reason, reflected by morality and laws, or nature, codified in one’s genes, from
being determinant, it attributes to the environment a fundamental part in the motivation of
Guedes 65
human actions. This view makes one’s actions dependent less on reason or nature and more
on the circumstances leading to an action.
The environment becomes as important a parameter as nature and reason in influ-
encing human behaviour. Once the conflict of nature and reason cannot be denied nor can
their coexistence, the environment presents itself as a compelling force in the configuration
of good and evil actions. A sense of causality lies outside the individual. The conditions to
which one is submitted lead one to take a course of action. These conditions, whether they
are right or wrong, influence one to do good or evil.
This approach seems coherent inasmuch as it does not consider the environment as
the only influence on human actions. Otherwise, it would justify the atrocities committed by
“good” men and excuse them from their moral responsibilities. Men would simply be victims
of an oppressive and hostile context that forces them to act offhandedly and wrongly. They
would merely react to an unfriendly setting, indifferent to the consequences of their actions.
Thus, attributing solely to the environment the cause of one’s actions is to corroborate the
view that men cannot be blamed for their acts. This mistake stems from a view that allows
one to think of good and evil as purely circumstantial.
Although modern thinkers, who also draw from Darwin’s ideas, return to the role of
nature in determining good and evil actions, they introduce novel apparatuses for critical
thinking. The biologist and naturalist Lyall Watson puts forward a natural history of good
and evil without the filter of religion and moral philosophy. Unlike Nietzsche’s approach in
On the Genealogy of Morals, he explains the topic based on the tenets of evolutionary biology,
anthropology, and psychology. Watson says that understanding evil from a cultural view does
not grasp its real character, although in fiction Robert Louis Stevenson comes close to it (xi).
His studies concentrate on the analysis of the gene.
Watson claims that what people term evil is in fact biological. To ascribe evil to na-
ture is still a current practice and Watson is not alone in this line of thought. Roy W. Perret
also attributes evil to human nature, “a character-based notion” (305). He believes that evil
Guedes 66
actions stem from a corrupt natural disposition and a flawed personality. Watson claims that
from a natural perspective, good and evil do not exist except to the eyes of culture. He says
that if good does exist, it cannot be natural. Nature can only be evil as a rule of thumb, be-
cause genes can only be selfish.
12
Watson uses genes as a metaphor to explain natural behaviour. Following the steps
of the evolutionary biologists Richard Dawkins, William Donald Hamilton, and Edward
Osborne Wilson, he describes genes as structures present in every complex living creature.
He uses the term gene for all the imperative instinctive forces of an individual to explain
human natural behaviour as selfish (Dark 57). He affirms that the gene is devoid of direction
and intelligence, and selfishness is the main characteristic that makes evil possible from a
cultural perspective. “Genes are simple-minded and mean-spirited. They have no vision and
cannot be expected to have the welfare of the whole species at heart [. . .] Generosity and
unselfishness are not part of biological nature. Where such things exist, they have had to be
learnt or cultured by working against the trend. The sad fact is that we are born selfish” (54).
Watson believes that genes leave no room for altruism, which can only be unnatural. He
shows that, from a natural perspective, the gene can only act in ways that it can benefit in
order to survive. Selfishness is the gene’s sole character and guiding force. Watson supports
his claim based on the study of animal behaviour, which shows selfishness according to three
basic genetic rules.
The first rule is “be nasty to outsiders.” According to this principle, a gene behaves
in such a way to benefit from the action of others that have no kinship to them, which are
total strangers to them, that is, that are out of their gene pool. Watson illustrates this point by
telling how non-related penguins act when they feel threatened. On their way to the sea full
of leopard seals, which are their major predators, some penguins make way for more anxious
penguins to take the plunge into the water. They do it as if out of politeness, when in fact all
they want is to check the risk of becoming prey. These penguins make guinea pigs out of
12
The theory of the selfish gene is expounded in Richard Dawkins’s The Selfish Gene.
Guedes 67
others in order to preserve themselves. From a cultural viewpoint, this behaviour is an ex-
ample of cowardice and selfishness. Had any of the penguins been related, the story might
have been otherwise.
The second principle is “be nice to insiders.” Being kind to strangers seems unnatu-
ral, and it means wasted energy and unnecessary risk, according to Watson. Nonetheless,
being kind or “nice” to insiders makes biological sense, although “nice” may not be the most
appropriate word to describe this attitude. Genes do not worry about anything except how
well their gene pool is represented; they worry about preserving and strengthening their own
biological inheritance. Thus, they do not protect a brother for the sake of kindness or be-
cause they are nice. Rather genes protect a brother because otherwise half of their represen-
tatives are dismissed if the brother dies. Genes only start to murder their own family if there
is a higher gain.
The third principle is “cheat whenever possible.” Watson outlines that genes will do
anything possible to benefit from a situation regardless of the other. Studying wild hyenas in
Kenya, Laurence Frank found the reason for the fatal fight between siblings. Female hyenas
play the dominant role in their social life and they usually have twins. If one of the siblings is
a female, the fight is justified because it means that this female winner will eliminate the
competition and will be the top ranked hyena in a group, being able to spread its gene pool
more effectively. However, if the sibling is male, he is spared as he is not in direct competi-
tion to the female sibling. Any gene, Frank says, will take advantage of another less cautious
gene if he is given the chance: “No chick, no pup, no body ever passes up an opportunity to
deceive. They pretend to be younger, hungrier, and more at risk than they really are in the
hope of getting more time, more food, or more attention” (65). No one escapes the talent to
lie; deceit and pretence are key words for the third principle. Another compelling evidence
that cheating occurs more often than one imagines is camouflage. Watson claims that cam-
ouflage can be defined as “the communication of misinformation” (70). He also points out
that “no system of communication in any species is designed to convey the truth, the whole
Guedes 68
truth and nothing but the truth” (72). From such a lawful perspective, this particular flair for
deception or even the ability to hide reveals itself as a form of cheating.
Hyde is the embodiment of Jekyll’s nature. Hyde is moved by selfishness and indi-
vidualism, which is illustrated in the way he is always callous with others, much like how
genes behave in order to survive. In a natural world, his conduct is not out of place but in a
cultural setting, it acquires the main characteristic that seems to define evil actions. Neither
altruism nor social attachment concern Hyde at any time; he shows no sign of guilt or re-
morse because such feelings do not belong to the natural realm.
Overall, the theory of evolution applied to Jekyll and Hyde amplifies one of the ways
good and evil can be understood in literature. It shows the relevance that the environment
acquires in imposing on men certain types of conduct that at times are considered good and
at other times are classed evil. Nonetheless, to think that this environment exists independ-
ently as an external reality imposing its own terms on men would make matters too simple.
The environment must be considered, along with nature and reason, that is, genetic and cul-
tural codes, to assess men’s actions as good or evil.
Guedes 69
6. Conclusion
Although Stevenson does not present a solution to the case of Jekyll and Hyde, he
puts at issue the problem of good and evil actions in ways that go beyond the apparent con-
tradistinctions found in the text. Outstripping the noticeable dichotomies that riddle the
story, such as those of nature and reason, God and Devil or human and animal, he allows
one to make a substantial analysis of human behaviour, posing questions on how good and
evil are discriminated. These questions bring out elements that make up for a more compre-
hensive outlook of the topic.
Stevenson’s use of the double permits a confrontation of Kantian and Nietzschean
formulations on morality. The approximation of the categorical imperative to Jekyll is hin-
dered by his ambiguity and his incoherence, possibly suggesting the corrosion of premises
that supported the morality proposed by Kant, or else, a resistance to their application in an
extreme way. These premises are that morality must be rational and that, as such, they must
be the same for all rational beings independent of circumstances and conditions, as Alasdair
MacIntyre puts it. Such emphasis on reason becomes an obstacle to Jekyll since he cannot
epitomize pure reason.
The approximation of the second formulation to Hyde is less of an obstacle due to
the similarities found between the Übermensch and Hyde. However, the assumptions imbued
with Nietzsche’s Übermensch are not shown as an alternative to a Kantian moral philosophy
but rather as an effect of the boundless effort to privilege reason. They are presented as the
spoils of an over-rationalizing tendency in society; they are introduced as a reaction to the
abandoning of nature; they are rescued in a radical attempt to give human nature the atten-
tion it had lost. Hence, the monstrosity imputed to Hyde.
Nietzsche’s acute focus on human nature allows an approach to Darwin’s theory of
evolution, although Nietzsche does not discuss nature in biological terms as Darwin does. In
Kant and Nietzsche, there is the idea that morality comes from the individual. In Kant, this
Guedes 70
morality will privilege the collectivity, whereas in Nietzsche, it will focus on the self. In both
cases, the source of moral actions is internal and independent from external elements. In
Darwin, external factors are taken into account.
From an evolutionary viewpoint, Darwin offers an understanding of society that puts
chance and the environment as key elements because they also determine human actions.
The social boundaries and moral values within a society do not always originate from every
individual. As much as individuals define them, they also define individuals. These social
boundaries and moral values are also inherited by and enforced on men. They are often im-
posed by the law and other cultural institutions in ways that determine human actions, in
ways that encourage some types of actions and halt others; in ways that stimulate the use of
reason and reduce the role of nature so that life in a community becomes possible. Thus,
social development makes evolutionary sense.
Based on these analyses, three propositions can be used to assess good and evil ac-
tions. The first, based on Kant, entails the emphasis on reason as the foundation of an abso-
lute morality, which has freedom and collectivity as its main tenets. Morality’s ultimate goal is
true satisfaction. Within this view, altruism becomes the parameter from which to evaluate
human actions, rendering them as good if they represent selflessness and evil if they convey
the opposite. Nature is set aside.
The second proposition, predicated by Nietzsche, puts nature in the place of impor-
tance that reason occupied. It dismisses morality and the way it is understood by Kant to
focus on nature and the self. It privileges individualism and freedom from rules, making
power the sole criterion against which human actions are measured. Good actions turn out
to be those that engender one’s nature whereas evil actions become those that demur nature.
The third proposition includes an element that does not exempt reason and nature
from determining human behaviour but accentuates the role of the environment in shaping
it. Rooted in Darwin, these notions take into account the forces that compel individuals to
adapt to their surroundings in a natural process that will allow life in society to continue.
Guedes 71
Therefore, good actions differ from evil ones according to the extent they lead an individual
to adjust to his environment.
Lyall Watson offers a modern approach to good and evil that distinguishes a cultural
from a natural perspective, claiming that if actions based on nature must be categorized by
culture in those terms, they will be classed as evil because nature can only be selfish. By con-
trast, his view endorses the part reason plays in making life in society possible through the
creation of a set of morals that is shared by men. According to MacIntyre, “the goods, and
with them the only grounds for authority of laws and virtues, can only be discovered by en-
tering into those relationships which constitute communities whose central bond is a shared
vision of an understanding of goods” (258). Good actions become attainable only when a
group shares them. Otherwise, if they were personal as Nietzsche attempts to make them in
the Übermensch, the assessment of human actions would turn out to be a matter of perspec-
tive. “[T]o isolate oneself from the communities,” MacIntyre states, is “to debar oneself from
finding any good outside of oneself. [It is] to condemn oneself to that moral solipsism which
constitutes Nietzschean greatness” (258). In this case, good actions can only be judged
against individual criteria, having no external reference. Therefore, a shared morality must
exist that provides the external reference with which actions may be evaluated.
MacIntyre also criticizes Kant for proposing a notion of duty in the categorical im-
perative that does not consider the consequences of one’s actions. MacIntyre believes that
the notion of duty Kant proposes suggests that “given a proposed course of action, [one]
may only ask whether, in doing it, one can consistently will that it shall be universally done,
and not ask what ends or purposes it serves” (198). This line of thought only leads to con-
formism to authority because this type of behaviour does not question the law or tries to
understand why the law requires such and such. He thinks that Kant fails in attempting to
prove that duty is independent from circumstances. Thus, Kantian and Nietzschean perspec-
tives do not succeed in presenting an encompassing set of criteria to evaluate human actions by
Guedes 72
themselves because the role of circumstance is neglected. Stevenson’s Jekyll and Hyde allows a
close analysis of these criteria and shows positive and negative aspects of Victorian morality.
Overall, on the positive side is morality’s power to make life in society possible by
means of rules. Men can live socially only when they are limited by laws that keep them from
harming each other and that bond them together. On the negative side, Stevenson observes
how the strict application of extreme rules of behaviour eventually fails. Within the highly
moral standards Jekyll must live, there is no space for the expression of nature or no mecha-
nism that allows room for its manifestation. Jekyll cannot cope with the demanding envi-
ronment he finds himself in. Stevenson depicts reason and nature as inseparable with Jekyll’s
failure attempt to purify himself from his nature. Men cannot bear the burden of total con-
trol. Since reason and nature coexist, nature must occasionally be granted safe leave. Society
must create mechanisms through which this unmediated side of men can be purged from
time to time so that a balance is found. It is on the balance of these conflicting parts in men
that morality should rest.
Further research could investigate authors that take into account other parameters to
define good and evil actions and apply them to Jekyll and Hyde and other literary pieces. Fu-
ture works could not only explore how the representation of this topic has changed in litera-
ture after Stevenson,
revealing literary goods and evils, but also lay bare the underlying struc-
ture on which the concepts of good and evil are built and sustained.
Guedes 73
7. Works Cited
Abrams, M. H. et al., eds. The Norton Anthology of English Literature. London: Norton, 1986.
Ambrosini, Richard & Richard Dury, eds. Robert Louis Stevenson: Writer of Boundaries. Madison:
The U of Wisconsin P, 2006.
Augustine. The City of God. Trans. Henry Bettenson. London: Penguin, 1984.
Calder, Jenni. Literary Contexts: Doubles, Devils and Monsters. Stevenson 126 -128.
Carroll, Joseph. Literary Darwinism: Evolution, Human Nature and Literature. New York:
Routledge, 2004.
Carroll, Noël. The Philosophy of Horror or Paradoxes of the Heart. New York: Routledge, 1990.
Cohen, Jeffrey Jerome, ed. Monster Theory: Reading Culture. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P,
1996.
Cohen, Patricia. “A Split Emerges as Conservatives Discuss Darwin.” The New York Times. 5
May 2007. 6 May 2007. <www.nytimes.com/2007/05/05/us/politics/
05darwin.html>
Christ, Carol, ed. The Victorian Age. New York: Norton, 1999. Vol. 2B of The Norton Anthology
of English Literature. 7
th
ed. 2 vols. 1043-1896.
Darwin, Charles. The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured
Races in the Struggle for Life. 6
th
ed. London: John Murray, 1872.
Dawkins, Richard. The Selfish Gene. New York: Oxford UP, 2006.
Dryden, Linda . The Modern Gothic and Literary Doubles. Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2004.
Dury, Richard. “Critical Reception”. The Robert Louis Stevenson Website. 30 Abr. 2007 <di-
namico.unibg.it/rls/critrec.htm>
Fielder, Leslie. Freaks: Myths and Images of the Secret Self. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1978.
Freud, Sigmund. “The Uncanny.” Literary Theory: an Anthology. Ed. Julie Rivkin and Michael
Ryan. Malden: Blackwell, 1998. 154-67.
Guedes 74
Gilmore, David D. Monsters: Evil Beings Mythical Beasts, and All Manners of Imaginary Terrors.
Philadelphia: U of Pennsylvania P, 2003.
Gould, Stephen Jay. “Post Darwinian Theories of the Ape within.” Stevenson 132-34.
Halberstam, Judith. “An Introduction to Gothic Monstrosity.” Stevenson 128-31.
Jeha, Julio. “Evil and Suffering in Auster, DeLillo, Doctorow and Vonnegut.”
www.juliojeha.pro.br. 6 Mar. 2003 Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais. 7 Aug.
2005. <www.juliojeha.pro.br/research_pgs/evil/evil_00201.htm >
Kant, Immanuel. Practical Philosophy. Ed. and trans. Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge
UP, 1996.
Kearney, Richard. Strangers, Gods and Monsters: Interpreting Otherness. New York: Routledge,
2003.
Kreuter, Peter Mario, ed. Monsters and the Monstrous: Myths and Metaphors of Enduring Evil. Ox-
ford, UK: Interdisciplinary-Press, 2004. 215-29.
Landow, George P. The Victorian Web. 20 Nov. 2006 <www.victorianweb.org>
Larrimore, Mark, ed. The Problem of Evil: A Reader. Padstow: Blackwell, 2001.
Linehan, Katherine. Preface. Stevenson xi–xv.
MacIntyre, Alsdair. A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to
the Twentieth Century. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1996.
---. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Indiana: U of Notre Dame P, 1984.
Massey, Irving. The Gaping Pig: Literature and Metamorphosis. Berkley: U of California P, 1976.
Mill, John Stuart. “Utilitarianism.” On Liberty and Utilitarianism. New York: Knopf, 1992. 113-
72. (Everyman’s Library 81)
Miller, Karl. Doubles: Studies in Literary History. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1985.
Mora, José Ferrater. Dicionário de Filosofia. Trans. Maria Stela Gonçalves et al. São Paulo:
Loyola, 2001.
Neiman, Susan. Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy. Princeton: Prince-
ton UP, 2002. 203-335.
Guedes 75
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. Trans. R. J. Hollingdale. London: Penguin, 1990.
---. The Birth of Tragedy. 1871. Trans. Ian Johnstone. June 2003. Malaspina University College.
7 Aug. 2006. <www.mala.bc.ca/~Johnstoi/Nietzsche/tragedy_all.htm>
---. Genealogy of Morals. Trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage,
1989.
---. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. London: Penguin, 2003.
---. The Anti-Christ. Trans. H. L. Mencken. Tucson: See Sharp Press, 1999.
Perret, Roy W. “Evil and Human Nature.” The Monist 85.2 (2002): 304-19.
Rank, Otto. “The Double as Immortal Self.”. Beyond Psychology. Philadelphia: E. Hauser, 1941.
New York: Dover, 1958. 62-101.
Reid, Julia. “Stevenson, Romance, and Evolutionary Psychology.” Ambrosini & Dury 215-
27.
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky. The Coherence of Gothic Conventions. New York: Routledge, 1986.
Stevenson, Robert Louis. Strange Case of Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde. 1886 .Ed. Katherine Linehan.
New York: Norton, 2002.
Turnbull, Olena M. “Robert Louis Stevenson and Nineteenth-Century Theories of Evolu-
tion: Crossing the Boundaries between Ideas and Art.” Ambrosini & Dury 228-36.
Walkowitz, Judith R. and Walter Houghton. “Sociohistorical Contexts: Political Disnudity
and Moral Conformity.” Stevenson 141-49.
Watson, Lyall. Dark Nature: A Natural History of Evil. New York: Harper Collins, 1997.
Wolfe. Charles T. Monsters and Philosophy. London: College Publications, 2005.
Wynne-Davies, Marion, ed. The Bloomsbury Guide to English Literature. London: Prentice Hall,
1990.
Livros Grátis
( http://www.livrosgratis.com.br )
Milhares de Livros para Download:
Baixar livros de Administração
Baixar livros de Agronomia
Baixar livros de Arquitetura
Baixar livros de Artes
Baixar livros de Astronomia
Baixar livros de Biologia Geral
Baixar livros de Ciência da Computação
Baixar livros de Ciência da Informação
Baixar livros de Ciência Política
Baixar livros de Ciências da Saúde
Baixar livros de Comunicação
Baixar livros do Conselho Nacional de Educação - CNE
Baixar livros de Defesa civil
Baixar livros de Direito
Baixar livros de Direitos humanos
Baixar livros de Economia
Baixar livros de Economia Doméstica
Baixar livros de Educação
Baixar livros de Educação - Trânsito
Baixar livros de Educação Física
Baixar livros de Engenharia Aeroespacial
Baixar livros de Farmácia
Baixar livros de Filosofia
Baixar livros de Física
Baixar livros de Geociências
Baixar livros de Geografia
Baixar livros de História
Baixar livros de Línguas
Baixar livros de Literatura
Baixar livros de Literatura de Cordel
Baixar livros de Literatura Infantil
Baixar livros de Matemática
Baixar livros de Medicina
Baixar livros de Medicina Veterinária
Baixar livros de Meio Ambiente
Baixar livros de Meteorologia
Baixar Monografias e TCC
Baixar livros Multidisciplinar
Baixar livros de Música
Baixar livros de Psicologia
Baixar livros de Química
Baixar livros de Saúde Coletiva
Baixar livros de Serviço Social
Baixar livros de Sociologia
Baixar livros de Teologia
Baixar livros de Trabalho
Baixar livros de Turismo